History of artificial intelligence

(Redirected from History of AI)

The history of artificial intelligence (AI) began in antiquity, with myths, stories, and rumors of artificial beings endowed with intelligence or consciousness by master craftsmen. The study of logic and formal reasoning from antiquity to the present led directly to the invention of the programmable digital computer in the 1940s, a machine based on abstract mathematical reasoning. This device and the ideas behind it inspired scientists to begin discussing the possibility of building an electronic brain.

The field of AI research was founded at a workshop held on the campus of Dartmouth College in 1956.[1] Attendees of the workshop became the leaders of AI research for decades. Many of them predicted that machines as intelligent as humans would exist within a generation. The U.S. government provided millions of dollars with the hope of making this vision come true.[2]

Eventually, it became obvious that researchers had grossly underestimated the difficulty of this feat.[3] In 1974, criticism from James Lighthill and pressure from the U.S. Congress led the U.S. and British Governments to stop funding undirected research into artificial intelligence. Seven years later, a visionary initiative by the Japanese Government and the success of expert systems reinvigorated investment in AI, and by the late 1980s, the industry had grown into a billion-dollar enterprise. However, investors' enthusiasm waned in the 1990s, and the field was criticized in the press and avoided by industry (a period known as an "AI winter"). Nevertheless, research and funding continued to grow under other names.

In the early 2000s, machine learning was applied to a wide range of problems in academia and industry. The success was due to the availability of powerful computer hardware, the collection of immense data sets, and the application of solid mathematical methods. Soon after, deep learning proved to be a breakthrough technology, eclipsing all other methods. The transformer architecture debuted in 2017 and was used to produce impressive generative AI applications, amongst other use cases. Investment in AI boomed in the 2020s.

Precursors

edit

Mythical, fictional, and speculative precursors

edit

Myth and legend

edit

In Greek mythology, Talos was a giant made of bronze who acted as guardian for the island of Crete. He would throw boulders at the ships of invaders and would complete 3 circuits around the island's perimeter daily.[4] According to pseudo-Apollodorus' Bibliotheke, Hephaestus forged Talos with the aid of a cyclops and presented the automaton as a gift to Minos.[5] In the Argonautica, Jason and the Argonauts defeated Talos by removing a plug near his foot, causing the vital ichor to flow out from his body and rendering him lifeless.[6]

Pygmalion was a legendary king and sculptor of Greek mythology, famously represented in Ovid's Metamorphoses. In the 10th book of Ovid's narrative poem, Pygmalion becomes disgusted with women when he witnesses the way in which the Propoetides prostitute themselves. Despite this, he makes offerings at the temple of Venus asking the goddess to bring to him a woman just like a statue he carved.[7]

Medieval legends of artificial beings

edit
 
Depiction of a homunculus from Goethe's Faust

In Of the Nature of Things, the Swiss alchemist Paracelsus describes a procedure that he claims can fabricate an "artificial man". By placing the "sperm of a man" in horse dung, and feeding it the "Arcanum of Mans blood" after 40 days, the concoction will become a living infant.[8]

The earliest written account regarding golem-making is found in the writings of Eleazar ben Judah of Worms in the early 13th century.[9] During the Middle Ages, it was believed that the animation of a Golem could be achieved by insertion of a piece of paper with any of God's names on it, into the mouth of the clay figure.[10] Unlike legendary automata like Brazen Heads,[11] a Golem was unable to speak.[12]

Takwin, the artificial creation of life, was a frequent topic of Ismaili alchemical manuscripts, especially those attributed to Jabir ibn Hayyan. Islamic alchemists attempted to create a broad range of life through their work, ranging from plants to animals.[13]

In Faust: The Second Part of the Tragedy by Johann Wolfgang von Goethe, an alchemically fabricated homunculus, destined to live forever in the flask in which he was made, endeavors to be born into a full human body. Upon the initiation of this transformation, however, the flask shatters and the homunculus dies.[14]

Modern fiction

edit

By the 19th century, ideas about artificial men and thinking machines became a popular theme in fiction. Notable works like Mary Shelley's Frankenstein and Karel Čapek's R.U.R. (Rossum's Universal Robots)[15] explored the concept of artificial life. Speculative essays, such as Samuel Butler's "Darwin among the Machines",[16] and Edgar Allan Poe's "Maelzel's Chess Player"[17] reflected society's growing interest in machines with artificial intelligence. AI remains a common topic in science fiction today.[18]

Automata

edit
 
Al-Jazari's programmable automata (1206 CE)

Realistic humanoid automata were built by craftsman from many civilizations, including Yan Shi,[19] Hero of Alexandria,[20] Al-Jazari,[21] Haroun al-Rashid,[22] Jacques de Vaucanson,[23][24] Leonardo Torres y Quevedo,[25] Pierre Jaquet-Droz and Wolfgang von Kempelen.[26][27]

The oldest known automata were the sacred statues of ancient Egypt and Greece.[28][29] The faithful believed that craftsman had imbued these figures with very real minds, capable of wisdom and emotion—Hermes Trismegistus wrote that "by discovering the true nature of the gods, man has been able to reproduce it".[30] English scholar Alexander Neckham asserted that the Ancient Roman poet Virgil had built a palace with automaton statues.[31]

During the early modern period, these legendary automata were said to possess the magical ability to answer questions put to them. The late medieval alchemist and proto-protestant Roger Bacon was purported to have fabricated a brazen head, having developed a legend of having been a wizard.[32][33] These legends were similar to the Norse myth of the Head of Mímir. According to legend, Mímir was known for his intellect and wisdom, and was beheaded in the Æsir-Vanir War. Odin is said to have "embalmed" the head with herbs and spoke incantations over it such that Mímir's head remained able to speak wisdom to Odin. Odin then kept the head near him for counsel.[34]

Formal reasoning

edit

Artificial intelligence is based on the assumption that the process of human thought can be mechanized. The study of mechanical—or "formal"—reasoning has a long history. Chinese, Indian and Greek philosophers all developed structured methods of formal deduction by the first millennium BCE. Their ideas were developed over the centuries by philosophers such as Aristotle (who gave a formal analysis of the syllogism),[35] Euclid (whose Elements was a model of formal reasoning), al-Khwārizmī (who developed algebra and gave his name to the word algorithm) and European scholastic philosophers such as William of Ockham and Duns Scotus.[36]

Spanish philosopher Ramon Llull (1232–1315) developed several logical machines devoted to the production of knowledge by logical means;[37][38] Llull described his machines as mechanical entities that could combine basic and undeniable truths by simple logical operations, produced by the machine by mechanical meanings, in such ways as to produce all the possible knowledge.[39] Llull's work had a great influence on Gottfried Leibniz, who redeveloped his ideas.[40]

 
Gottfried Leibniz, who speculated that human reason could be reduced to mechanical calculation

In the 17th century, Leibniz, Thomas Hobbes and René Descartes explored the possibility that all rational thought could be made as systematic as algebra or geometry.[41] Hobbes famously wrote in Leviathan: "For reason ... is nothing but reckoning, that is adding and subtracting".[42] Leibniz envisioned a universal language of reasoning, the characteristica universalis, which would reduce argumentation to calculation so that "there would be no more need of disputation between two philosophers than between two accountants. For it would suffice to take their pencils in hand, down to their slates, and to say each other (with a friend as witness, if they liked): Let us calculate."[43] These philosophers had begun to articulate the physical symbol system hypothesis that would become the guiding faith of AI research.

The study of mathematical logic provided the essential breakthrough that made artificial intelligence seem plausible. The foundations had been set by such works as Boole's The Laws of Thought and Frege's Begriffsschrift.[44] Building on Frege's system, Russell and Whitehead presented a formal treatment of the foundations of mathematics in their masterpiece, the Principia Mathematica in 1913. Inspired by Russell's success, David Hilbert challenged mathematicians of the 1920s and 30s to answer this fundamental question: "can all of mathematical reasoning be formalized?"[36] His question was answered by Gödel's incompleteness proof,[45] Turing's machine[45] and Church's Lambda calculus.[a]

 
US Army photo of the ENIAC at the Moore School of Electrical Engineering[47]

Their answer was surprising in two ways. First, they proved that there were, in fact, limits to what mathematical logic could accomplish. But second (and more important for AI) their work suggested that, within these limits, any form of mathematical reasoning could be mechanized. The Church-Turing thesis implied that a mechanical device, shuffling symbols as simple as 0 and 1, could imitate any conceivable process of mathematical deduction.[45] The key insight was the Turing machine—a simple theoretical construct that captured the essence of abstract symbol manipulation.[48] This invention would inspire a handful of scientists to begin discussing the possibility of thinking machines.

Computer science

edit

Calculating machines were designed or built in antiquity and throughout history by many people, including Gottfried Leibniz,[38][49] Joseph Marie Jacquard,[50] Charles Babbage,[50][51] Percy Ludgate,[52] Leonardo Torres Quevedo,[53] Vannevar Bush,[54] and others. Ada Lovelace speculated that Babbage's machine was "a thinking or ... reasoning machine", but warned "It is desirable to guard against the possibility of exaggerated ideas that arise as to the powers" of the machine.[55][56]

The first modern computers were the massive machines of the Second World War (such as Konrad Zuse's Z3, Alan Turing's Heath Robinson and Colossus, Atanasoff and Berry's and ABC and ENIAC at the University of Pennsylvania).[57] ENIAC was based on the theoretical foundation laid by Alan Turing and developed by John von Neumann,[58] and proved to be the most influential.[57]

Birth of artificial intelligence (1941-56)

edit
 
The IBM 702: a computer used by the first generation of AI researchers.

The earliest research into thinking machines was inspired by a confluence of ideas that became prevalent in the late 1930s, 1940s, and early 1950s. Recent research in neurology had shown that the brain was an electrical network of neurons that fired in all-or-nothing pulses. Norbert Wiener's cybernetics described control and stability in electrical networks. Claude Shannon's information theory described digital signals (i.e., all-or-nothing signals). Alan Turing's theory of computation showed that any form of computation could be described digitally. The close relationship between these ideas suggested that it might be possible to construct an "electronic brain".

In the 1940s and 50s, a handful of scientists from a variety of fields (mathematics, psychology, engineering, economics and political science) explored several research directions that would be vital to later AI research.[59] Alan Turing was among the first people to seriously investigate the theoretical possibility of "machine intelligence".[60] The field of "artificial intelligence research" was founded as an academic discipline in 1956.[61]

 
Turing test[62]

Turing Test

edit

In 1950 Turing published a landmark paper "Computing Machinery and Intelligence", in which he speculated about the possibility of creating machines that think.[63][b] In the paper, he noted that "thinking" is difficult to define and devised his famous Turing Test: If a machine could carry on a conversation (over a teleprinter) that was indistinguishable from a conversation with a human being, then it was reasonable to say that the machine was "thinking".[64] This simplified version of the problem allowed Turing to argue convincingly that a "thinking machine" was at least plausible and the paper answered all the most common objections to the proposition.[65] The Turing Test was the first serious proposal in the philosophy of artificial intelligence.

Artificial neural networks

edit

Walter Pitts and Warren McCulloch analyzed networks of idealized artificial neurons and showed how they might perform simple logical functions in 1943. They were the first to describe what later researchers would call a neural network.[66] The paper was influenced by Turing's paper 'On Computable Numbers' from 1936 using similar two-state boolean 'neurons', but was the first to apply it to neuronal function.[60] One of the students inspired by Pitts and McCulloch was Marvin Minsky who was a 24-year-old graduate student at the time. In 1951 Minsky and Dean Edmonds built the first neural net machine, the SNARC.[67] Minsky would later become one of the most important leaders and innovators in AI.

Cybernetic robots

edit

Experimental robots such as W. Grey Walter's turtles and the Johns Hopkins Beast, were built in the 1950s. These machines did not use computers, digital electronics or symbolic reasoning; they were controlled entirely by analog circuitry.[68]

Game AI

edit

In 1951, using the Ferranti Mark 1 machine of the University of Manchester, Christopher Strachey wrote a checkers program[69] and Dietrich Prinz wrote one for chess.[70] Arthur Samuel's checkers program, the subject of his 1959 paper "Some Studies in Machine Learning Using the Game of Checkers", eventually achieved sufficient skill to challenge a respectable amateur.[71] Samuel's program was among the first uses of what would later be called machine learning.[72] Game AI would continue to be used as a measure of progress in AI throughout its history.

Symbolic reasoning and the Logic Theorist

edit
 
Herbert Simon (left) in a chess match against Allen Newell c. 1958

When access to digital computers became possible in the mid-fifties, a few scientists instinctively recognized that a machine that could manipulate numbers could also manipulate symbols and that the manipulation of symbols could well be the essence of human thought. This was a new approach to creating thinking machines.[73][74]

In 1955, Allen Newell and future Nobel Laureate Herbert A. Simon created the "Logic Theorist", with help from J. C. Shaw. The program would eventually prove 38 of the first 52 theorems in Russell and Whitehead's Principia Mathematica, and find new and more elegant proofs for some.[75] Simon said that they had "solved the venerable mind/body problem, explaining how a system composed of matter can have the properties of mind."[76][c] The symbolic reasoning paradigm they introduced would dominate AI research and funding until the middle 90s, as well as inspire the cognitive revolution.

Dartmouth Workshop

edit

The Dartmouth workshop of 1956 was a pivotal event that marked the formal inception of AI as an academic discipline.[61] It was organized by Marvin Minsky and John McCarthy, with the support of two senior scientists Claude Shannon and Nathan Rochester of IBM. The proposal for the conference stated they intended to test the assertion that "every aspect of learning or any other feature of intelligence can be so precisely described that a machine can be made to simulate it".[77][d] The term "Artificial Intelligence" was introduced by John McCarthy at the workshop.[e] The participants included Ray Solomonoff, Oliver Selfridge, Trenchard More, Arthur Samuel, Allen Newell and Herbert A. Simon, all of whom would create important programs during the first decades of AI research.[83][f] At the workshop Newell and Simon debuted the "Logic Theorist".[84] The workshop was the moment that AI gained its name, its mission, its first major success and its key players, and is widely considered the birth of AI.[g]

Cognitive revolution

edit

In the autumn of 1956, Newell and Simon also presented the Logic Theorist at a meeting of the Special Interest Group in Information Theory at the Massachusetts Institute of Technology (MIT). At the same meeting, Noam Chomsky discussed his generative grammar, and George Miller described his landmark paper "The Magical Number Seven, Plus or Minus Two". Miller wrote "I left the symposium with a conviction, more intuitive than rational, that experimental psychology, theoretical linguistics, and the computer simulation of cognitive processes were all pieces from a larger whole."[86][57]

This meeting was the beginning of the "cognitive revolution"—an interdisciplinary paradigm shift in psychology, philosophy, computer science and neuroscience. It inspired the creation of the sub-fields of symbolic artificial intelligence, generative linguistics, cognitive science, cognitive psychology, cognitive neuroscience and the philosophical schools of computationalism and functionalism. All these fields used related tools to model the mind and results discovered in one field were relevant to the others.

The cognitive approach allowed researchers to consider "mental objects" like thoughts, plans, goals, facts or memories, often analyzed using high level symbols in functional networks. These objects had been forbidden as "unobservable" by earlier paradigms such as behaviorism.[h] Symbolic mental objects would become the major focus of AI research and funding for the next several decades.

Early successes (1956-1974)

edit

The programs developed in the years after the Dartmouth Workshop were, to most people, simply "astonishing":[i] computers were solving algebra word problems, proving theorems in geometry and learning to speak English. Few at the time would have believed that such "intelligent" behavior by machines was possible at all.[90][91][89] Researchers expressed an intense optimism in private and in print, predicting that a fully intelligent machine would be built in less than 20 years.[92] Government agencies like the Defense Advanced Research Projects Agency (DARPA, then known as "ARPA") poured money into the field.[93] Artificial Intelligence laboratories were set up at a number of British and US universities in the latter 1950s and early 1960s.[60]

Approaches

edit

There were many successful programs and new directions in the late 50s and 1960s. Among the most influential were these:

edit

Many early AI programs used the same basic algorithm. To achieve some goal (like winning a game or proving a theorem), they proceeded step by step towards it (by making a move or a deduction) as if searching through a maze, backtracking whenever they reached a dead end.[94] The principal difficulty was that, for many problems, the number of possible paths through the "maze" was astronomical (a situation known as a "combinatorial explosion"). Researchers would reduce the search space by using heuristics that would eliminate paths that were unlikely to lead to a solution.[95]

Newell and Simon tried to capture a general version of this algorithm in a program called the "General Problem Solver".[96][97] Other "searching" programs were able to accomplish impressive tasks like solving problems in geometry and algebra, such as Herbert Gelernter's Geometry Theorem Prover (1958)[98] and Symbolic Automatic Integrator (SAINT), written by Minsky's student James Slagle in 1961.[99][100] Other programs searched through goals and subgoals to plan actions, like the STRIPS system developed at Stanford to control the behavior of the robot Shakey.[101]

Natural language

edit
 
An example of a semantic network

An important goal of AI research is to allow computers to communicate in natural languages like English. An early success was Daniel Bobrow's program STUDENT, which could solve high school algebra word problems.[102]

A semantic net represents concepts (e.g. "house", "door") as nodes, and relations among concepts as links between the nodes (e.g. "has-a"). The first AI program to use a semantic net was written by Ross Quillian[103] and the most successful (and controversial) version was Roger Schank's Conceptual dependency theory.[104]

Joseph Weizenbaum's ELIZA could carry out conversations that were so realistic that users occasionally were fooled into thinking they were communicating with a human being and not a computer program (see ELIZA effect). But in fact, ELIZA simply gave a canned response or repeated back what was said to it, rephrasing its response with a few grammar rules. ELIZA was the first chatbot.[105][106]

Micro-worlds

edit

In the late 60s, Marvin Minsky and Seymour Papert of the MIT AI Laboratory proposed that AI research should focus on artificially simple situations known as micro-worlds.[j] They pointed out that in successful sciences like physics, basic principles were often best understood using simplified models like frictionless planes or perfectly rigid bodies. Much of the research focused on a "blocks world," which consists of colored blocks of various shapes and sizes arrayed on a flat surface.[107]

This paradigm led to innovative work in machine vision by Gerald Sussman, Adolfo Guzman, David Waltz (who invented "constraint propagation"), and especially Patrick Winston. At the same time, Minsky and Papert built a robot arm that could stack blocks, bringing the blocks world to life. Terry Winograd's SHRDLU could communicate in ordinary English sentences about the micro-world, plan operations and execute them.[107]

Perceptrons and early neural networks

edit

In the 1960s funding was primarily directed towards laboratories researching symbolic AI, however several people still pursued research in neural networks.

 
The Mark 1 Perceptron.

The perceptron, a single-layer neural network was introduced in 1958 by Frank Rosenblatt[108] (who had been a schoolmate of Marvin Minsky at the Bronx High School of Science).[109] Like most AI researchers, he was optimistic about their power, predicting that a perceptron "may eventually be able to learn, make decisions, and translate languages."[110] Rosenblatt was primarily funded by Office of Naval Research.[111]

Bernard Widrow and his student Ted Hoff built ADALINE (1960) and MADALINE (1962), which had up to 1000 adjustable weights.[112][113] A group at Stanford Research Institute led by Charles A. Rosen and Alfred E. (Ted) Brain built two neural network machines named MINOS I (1960) and II (1963), mainly funded by U.S. Army Signal Corps. MINOS II[114] had 6600 adjustable weights,[115] and was controlled with an SDS 910 computer in a configuration named MINOS III (1968), which could classify symbols on army maps, and recognize hand-printed characters on Fortran coding sheets.[116][117] Most of neural network research during this early period involved building and using bespoke hardware, rather than simulation on digital computers.[k]

However, partly due to lack of results and partly due to competition from symbolic AI research, the MINOS project ran out of funding in 1966. Rosenblatt failed to secure continued funding in the 1960s.[118] In 1969, research came to a sudden halt with the publication of Minsky and Papert's 1969 book Perceptrons.[119] It suggested that there were severe limitations to what perceptrons could do and that Rosenblatt's predictions had been grossly exaggerated. The effect of the book was that virtually no research was funded in connectionism for 10 years.[120] The competition for government funding ended with the victory of symbolic AI approaches over neural networks.[117][118]

Minsky (who had worked on SNARC) became a staunch objector to pure connectionist AI. Widrow (who had worked on ADALINE) turned to adaptive signal processing. The SRI group (which worked on MINOS) turned to symbolic AI and robotics.[117][118]

The main problem was the inability to train multilayered networks (versions of backpropagation had already been used in other fields but it was unknown to these researchers).[121][120] The AI community became aware of backpropogation in the 80s,[122] and, in the 21st century, neural networks would become enormously successful, fulfilling all of Rosenblatt's optimistic predictions. Rosenblatt did not live to see this, however, as he died in a boating accident in 1971.[123]

Optimism

edit

The first generation of AI researchers made these predictions about their work:

  • 1958, H. A. Simon and Allen Newell: "within ten years a digital computer will be the world's chess champion" and "within ten years a digital computer will discover and prove an important new mathematical theorem."[124]
  • 1965, H. A. Simon: "machines will be capable, within twenty years, of doing any work a man can do."[125]
  • 1967, Marvin Minsky: "Within a generation... the problem of creating 'artificial intelligence' will substantially be solved."[126]
  • 1970, Marvin Minsky (in Life magazine): "In from three to eight years we will have a machine with the general intelligence of an average human being."[127][l]

Financing

edit

In June 1963, MIT received a $2.2 million grant from the newly created Advanced Research Projects Agency (ARPA, later known as DARPA). The money was used to fund project MAC which subsumed the "AI Group" founded by Minsky and McCarthy five years earlier. DARPA continued to provide $3 million each year until the 70s.[130] DARPA made similar grants to Newell and Simon's program at Carnegie Mellon University and to Stanford University's AI Lab, founded by John McCarthy in 1963.[131] Another important AI laboratory was established at Edinburgh University by Donald Michie in 1965.[132] These four institutions would continue to be the main centers of AI research and funding in academia for many years.[133][m]

The money was given with few strings attached: J. C. R. Licklider, then the director of ARPA, believed that his organization should "fund people, not projects!" and allowed researchers to pursue whatever directions might interest them.[135] This created a freewheeling atmosphere at MIT that gave birth to the hacker culture,[136] but this "hands off" approach did not last.

First AI Winter (1974–1980)

edit

In the 1970s, AI was subject to critiques and financial setbacks. AI researchers had failed to appreciate the difficulty of the problems they faced. Their tremendous optimism had raised public expectations impossibly high, and when the promised results failed to materialize, funding targeted at AI was severely reduced.[137] The lack of success indicated the techniques being used by AI researchers at the time were insufficient to achieve their goals.[138][139]

These setbacks did not affect the growth and progress of the field, however. The funding cuts only impacted a handful of major laboratories[140] and the critiques were largely ignored.[141] General public interest in the field continued to grow,[140] the number of researchers increased dramatically,[140] and new ideas were explored in logic programming, commonsense reasoning and many other areas. Historian Thomas Haigh argued in 2023 that there was no winter,[140] and AI researcher Nils Nilsson described this period as the most "exciting" time to work in AI.[142]

Problems

edit

In the early seventies, the capabilities of AI programs were limited. Even the most impressive could only handle trivial versions of the problems they were supposed to solve;[n] all the programs were, in some sense, "toys".[144] AI researchers had begun to run into several limits that would be only conquered decades later, and others that still stymie the field in the 2020s:

  • Limited computer power: There was not enough memory or processing speed to accomplish anything truly useful.[o] For example: Ross Quillian's successful work on natural language was demonstrated with a vocabulary of only 20 words, because that was all that would fit in memory.[146] Hans Moravec argued in 1976 that computers were still millions of times too weak to exhibit intelligence. He suggested an analogy: artificial intelligence requires computer power in the same way that aircraft require horsepower. Below a certain threshold, it's impossible, but, as power increases, eventually it could become easy. "With enough horsepower," he wrote, "anything will fly".[147][p]
  • Intractability and the combinatorial explosion: In 1972 Richard Karp (building on Stephen Cook's 1971 theorem) showed there are many problems that can only be solved in exponential time. Finding optimal solutions to these problems requires extraordinary amounts of computer time, except when the problems are trivial. This limitation applied to all symbolic AI programs that used search trees and meant that many of the "toy" solutions used by AI would never scale to useful systems.[143][139]
  • Moravec's paradox: Early AI research had been very successful at getting computers to do "intelligent" tasks like proving theorems, solving geometry problems and playing chess. Their success at these intelligent tasks convinced them that the problem of intelligent behavior had been largely solved.[149][150] However, they utterly failed to make progress on "unintelligent" tasks like recognizing a face or crossing a room without bumping into anything.[149][151] By the 1980s, researchers would realize that symbolic reasoning was utterly unsuited for these perceptual and sensorimotor tasks and that there were limits to this approach.[150]
  • The breadth of commonsense knowledge: Many important artificial intelligence applications like vision or natural language require enormous amounts of information about the world: the program needs to have some idea of what it might be looking at or what it is talking about. This requires that the program know most of the same things about the world that a child does. Researchers soon discovered that this was a vast amount of information with billions of atomic facts. No one in 1970 could build a database large enough and no one knew how a program might learn so much information.[152]
  • Representing commonsense reasoning: A number of related problems[q] appeared when researchers tried to represent commonsense reasoning using formal logic or symbols. Descriptions of very ordinary deductions tended to get longer and longer the more one worked on them, as more and more exceptions, clarifications and distinctions were required.[r] However, when people thought about ordinary concepts they did not rely on precise definitions, rather they seemed to make hundreds of imprecise assumptions, correcting them when necessary using their entire body of commonsense knowledge. Gerald Sussman observed that "using precise language to describe essentially imprecise concepts doesn't make them any more precise."[153]

Decrease in funding

edit

The agencies which funded AI research, such as the British government, DARPA and the National Research Council (NRC) became frustrated with the lack of progress and eventually cut off almost all funding for undirected AI research. The pattern began in 1966 when the Automatic Language Processing Advisory Committee (ALPAC) report criticized machine translation efforts. After spending $20 million, the NRC ended all support.[154] In 1973, the Lighthill report on the state of AI research in the UK criticized the failure of AI to achieve its "grandiose objectives" and led to the dismantling of AI research in that country.[155] (The report specifically mentioned the combinatorial explosion problem as a reason for AI's failings.)[139][143][s] DARPA was deeply disappointed with researchers working on the Speech Understanding Research program at CMU and canceled an annual grant of $3 million.[157][t]

Hans Moravec blamed the crisis on the unrealistic predictions of his colleagues. "Many researchers were caught up in a web of increasing exaggeration."[158][u] However, there was another issue: since the passage of the Mansfield Amendment in 1969, DARPA had been under increasing pressure to fund "mission-oriented direct research, rather than basic undirected research". Funding for the creative, freewheeling exploration that had gone on in the 60s would not come from DARPA, which instead directed money at specific projects with clear objectives, such as autonomous tanks and battle management systems.[159][v]

The major laboratories (MIT, Stanford, CMU and Edinburgh) had been receiving generous support from their governments, and when it was withdrawn, these were the only places that were seriously impacted by the budget cuts. The thousands of researchers outside these institutions and the many more thousands that were joining the field were unaffected.[140]

Philosophical and ethical critiques

edit

Several philosophers had strong objections to the claims being made by AI researchers. One of the earliest was John Lucas, who argued that Gödel's incompleteness theorem showed that a formal system (such as a computer program) could never see the truth of certain statements, while a human being could.[161] Hubert Dreyfus ridiculed the broken promises of the 1960s and critiqued the assumptions of AI, arguing that human reasoning actually involved very little "symbol processing" and a great deal of embodied, instinctive, unconscious "know how".[w][163] John Searle's Chinese Room argument, presented in 1980, attempted to show that a program could not be said to "understand" the symbols that it uses (a quality called "intentionality"). If the symbols have no meaning for the machine, Searle argued, then the machine can not be described as "thinking".[164]

These critiques were not taken seriously by AI researchers. Problems like intractability and commonsense knowledge seemed much more immediate and serious. It was unclear what difference "know how" or "intentionality" made to an actual computer program. MIT's Minsky said of Dreyfus and Searle "they misunderstand, and should be ignored."[165] Dreyfus, who also taught at MIT, was given a cold shoulder: he later said that AI researchers "dared not be seen having lunch with me."[166] Joseph Weizenbaum, the author of ELIZA, was also an outspoken critic of Dreyfus' positions, but he "deliberately made it plain that [his AI colleagues' treatment of Dreyfus] was not the way to treat a human being,"[x] and was unprofessional and childish.[168]

Weizenbaum began to have serious ethical doubts about AI when Kenneth Colby wrote a "computer program which can conduct psychotherapeutic dialogue" based on ELIZA.[169][170][y] Weizenbaum was disturbed that Colby saw a mindless program as a serious therapeutic tool. A feud began, and the situation was not helped when Colby did not credit Weizenbaum for his contribution to the program. In 1976, Weizenbaum published Computer Power and Human Reason which argued that the misuse of artificial intelligence has the potential to devalue human life.[172]

Logic at Stanford, CMU and Edinburgh

edit

Logic was introduced into AI research as early as 1958, by John McCarthy in his Advice Taker proposal.[173][98] In 1963, J. Alan Robinson had discovered a simple method to implement deduction on computers, the resolution and unification algorithm.[98] However, straightforward implementations, like those attempted by McCarthy and his students in the late 1960s, were especially intractable: the programs required astronomical numbers of steps to prove simple theorems.[173][174] A more fruitful approach to logic was developed in the 1970s by Robert Kowalski at the University of Edinburgh, and soon this led to the collaboration with French researchers Alain Colmerauer and Philippe Roussel [fr] who created the successful logic programming language Prolog.[175] Prolog uses a subset of logic (Horn clauses, closely related to "rules" and "production rules") that permit tractable computation. Rules would continue to be influential, providing a foundation for Edward Feigenbaum's expert systems and the continuing work by Allen Newell and Herbert A. Simon that would lead to Soar and their unified theories of cognition.[176]

Critics of the logical approach noted, as Dreyfus had, that human beings rarely used logic when they solved problems. Experiments by psychologists like Peter Wason, Eleanor Rosch, Amos Tversky, Daniel Kahneman and others provided proof.[z] McCarthy responded that what people do is irrelevant. He argued that what is really needed are machines that can solve problems—not machines that think as people do.[aa]

MIT's "anti-logic" approach

edit

Among the critics of McCarthy's approach were his colleagues across the country at MIT. Marvin Minsky, Seymour Papert and Roger Schank were trying to solve problems like "story understanding" and "object recognition" that required a machine to think like a person. In order to use ordinary concepts like "chair" or "restaurant" they had to make all the same illogical assumptions that people normally made. Unfortunately, imprecise concepts like these are hard to represent in logic. MIT chose instead to focus on writing programs that solved a given task without using high-level abstract definitions or general theories of cognition, and measured performance by iterative testing, rather than arguments from first principles. Schank described their "anti-logic" approaches as scruffy, as opposed to the neat paradigm used by McCarthy, Kowalski, Feigenbaum, Newell and Simon.[177][ab]

In 1975, in a seminal paper, Minsky noted that many of his fellow researchers were using the same kind of tool: a framework that captures all our common sense assumptions about something. For example, if we use the concept of a bird, there is a constellation of facts that immediately come to mind: we might assume that it flies, eats worms and so on (none of which are true for all birds). Minsky associated these assumptions with the general category and they could be inherited by the frames for subcategories and individuals, or over-ridden as necessary. He called these structures frames. Schank used a version of frames he called "scripts" to successfully answer questions about short stories in English.[178] Frames would eventually be widely used in software engineering under the name object-oriented programming.

The logicians rose to the challenge. Pat Hayes claimed that "most of 'frames' is just a new syntax for parts of first-order logic." But he noted that "there are one or two apparently minor details which give a lot of trouble, however, especially defaults".[179]

Ray Reiter admitted that "conventional logics, such as first-order logic, lack the expressive power to adequately represent the knowledge required for reasoning by default".[180] He proposed augmenting first-order logic with a closed world assumption that a conclusion holds (by default) if its contrary cannot be shown. He showed how such an assumption corresponds to the common sense assumption made in reasoning with frames. He also showed that it has its "procedural equivalent" as negation as failure in Prolog. The closed world assumption, as formulated by Reiter, "is not a first-order notion. (It is a meta notion.)"[180] However, Keith Clark showed that negation as finite failure can be understood as reasoning implicitly with definitions in first-order logic including a unique name assumption that different terms denote different individuals.[181]

During the late 1970s and throughout the 1980s, a variety of logics and extensions of first-order logic were developed both for negation as failure in logic programming and for default reasoning more generally. Collectively, these logics have become known as non-monotonic logics.

Boom (1980–1987)

edit

In the 1980s, a form of AI program called "expert systems" was adopted by corporations around the world and knowledge became the focus of mainstream AI research. Governments provided substantial funding, such as Japan's fifth generation computer project and the U.S. Strategic Computing Initiative. "Overall, the AI industry boomed from a few million dollars in 1980 to billions of dollars in 1988."[122]

Expert systems become widely used

edit

An expert system is a program that answers questions or solves problems about a specific domain of knowledge, using logical rules that are derived from the knowledge of experts.[182] The earliest examples were developed by Edward Feigenbaum and his students. Dendral, begun in 1965, identified compounds from spectrometer readings.[183][120] MYCIN, developed in 1972, diagnosed infectious blood diseases.[122] They demonstrated the feasibility of the approach.

Expert systems restricted themselves to a small domain of specific knowledge (thus avoiding the commonsense knowledge problem)[120] and their simple design made it relatively easy for programs to be built and then modified once they were in place. All in all, the programs proved to be useful: something that AI had not been able to achieve up to this point.[184]

In 1980, an expert system called R1 was completed at CMU for the Digital Equipment Corporation. It was an enormous success: it was saving the company 40 million dollars annually by 1986.[185] Corporations around the world began to develop and deploy expert systems and by 1985 they were spending over a billion dollars on AI, most of it to in-house AI departments.[186] An industry grew up to support them, including hardware companies like Symbolics and Lisp Machines and software companies such as IntelliCorp and Aion.[187]

Government funding increases

edit

In 1981, the Japanese Ministry of International Trade and Industry set aside $850 million for the Fifth generation computer project. Their objectives were to write programs and build machines that could carry on conversations, translate languages, interpret pictures, and reason like human beings.[188] Much to the chagrin of scruffies, they initially chose Prolog as the primary computer language for the project.[189]

Other countries responded with new programs of their own. The UK began the £350 million Alvey project.[190] A consortium of American companies formed the Microelectronics and Computer Technology Corporation (or "MCC") to fund large scale projects in AI and information technology.[191][190] DARPA responded as well, founding the Strategic Computing Initiative and tripling its investment in AI between 1984 and 1988.[192][193]

Knowledge revolution

edit

The power of expert systems came from the expert knowledge they contained. They were part of a new direction in AI research that had been gaining ground throughout the 70s. "AI researchers were beginning to suspect—reluctantly, for it violated the scientific canon of parsimony—that intelligence might very well be based on the ability to use large amounts of diverse knowledge in different ways,"[194] writes Pamela McCorduck. "[T]he great lesson from the 1970s was that intelligent behavior depended very much on dealing with knowledge, sometimes quite detailed knowledge, of a domain where a given task lay".[195] Knowledge based systems and knowledge engineering became a major focus of AI research in the 1980s.[196] It was hoped that vast databases would solve the commonsense knowledge problem and provide the support that commonsense reasoning required.

In the 1980s some researchers attempted to attack the commonsense knowledge problem directly, by creating a massive database that would contain all the mundane facts that the average person knows. Douglas Lenat, who started a database called Cyc, argued that there is no shortcut ― the only way for machines to know the meaning of human concepts is to teach them, one concept at a time, by hand.[197]

New directions in the 1980s

edit

Although symbolic knowledge representation and logical reasoning produced useful applications in the 80s and received massive amounts of funding, it was still unable to solve problems in perception, robotics, learning and common sense. A small number of scientists and engineers began to doubt that the symbolic approach would ever be sufficient for these tasks and developed other approaches, such as "connectionism", robotics, "soft" computing and reinforcement learning. Nils Nilsson called these approaches "sub-symbolic".

Revival of neural networks: "connectionism"

edit
 
A Hopfield net with four nodes

In 1982, physicist John Hopfield was able to prove that a form of neural network (now called a "Hopfield net") could learn and process information, and provably converges after enough time under any fixed condition. It was a breakthrough, as it was previously thought that nonlinear networks would, in general, evolve chaotically.[198] Around the same time, Geoffrey Hinton and David Rumelhart popularized a method for training neural networks called "backpropagation".[ac] These two developments helped to revive the exploration of artificial neural networks.[122][199]

Neural networks, along with several other similar models, received widespread attention after the 1986 publication of the Parallel Distributed Processing, a two volume collection of papers edited by Rumelhart and psychologist James McClelland. The new field was christened "connectionism" and there was a considerable debate between advocates of symbolic AI the "connectionists".[122] Hinton called symbols the "luminous aether of AI" – that is, an unworkable and misleading model of intelligence.[122]

In 1990, Yann LeCun at Bell Labs used convolutional neural networks to recognize handwritten digits. The system was used widely in 90s, reading zip codes and personal checks. This was the first genuinely useful application of neural networks.[200][201]

Robotics and embodied reason

edit

Rodney Brooks, Hans Moravec and others argued that, in order to show real intelligence, a machine needs to have a body — it needs to perceive, move, survive and deal with the world.[202] Sensorimotor skills are essential to higher level skills such as commonsense reasoning. They can't be efficiently implemented using abstract symbolic reasoning, so AI should solve the problems of perception, mobility, manipulation and survival without using symbolic representation at all. These robotics researchers advocated building intelligence "from the bottom up".[ad]

A precursor to this idea was David Marr, who had come to MIT in the late 1970s from a successful background in theoretical neuroscience to lead the group studying vision. He rejected all symbolic approaches (both McCarthy's logic and Minsky's frames), arguing that AI needed to understand the physical machinery of vision from the bottom up before any symbolic processing took place. (Marr's work would be cut short by leukemia in 1980.)[204]

In his 1990 paper "Elephants Don't Play Chess,"[205] robotics researcher Brooks took direct aim at the physical symbol system hypothesis, arguing that symbols are not always necessary since "the world is its own best model. It is always exactly up to date. It always has every detail there is to be known. The trick is to sense it appropriately and often enough."[206]

In the 1980s and 1990s, many cognitive scientists also rejected the symbol processing model of the mind and argued that the body was essential for reasoning, a theory called the "embodied mind thesis".[207]

Soft computing and probabilistic reasoning

edit

Soft computing uses methods that work with incomplete and imprecise information. They do not attempt to give precise, logical answers, but give results that are only "probably" correct. This allowed them to solve problems that precise symbolic methods could not handle. Press accounts often claimed these tools could "think like a human".[208][209]

Judea Pearl's Probabilistic Reasoning in Intelligent Systems: Networks of Plausible Inference, an influential 1988 book[210] brought probability and decision theory into AI.[211] Fuzzy logic, developed by Lofti Zadeh in the 60s, began to be more widely used in AI and robotics. Evolutionary computation and artificial neural networks also handle imprecise information, and are classified as "soft". In the 90s and early 2000s many other soft computing tools were developed and put into use, including Bayesian networks,[211] hidden Markov models,[211] information theory and stochastic modeling. These tools in turn depended on advanced mathematical techniques such as classical optimization. For a time in the 1990s and early 2000s, these soft tools were studied by a subfield of AI called "computational intelligence".[212]

Reinforcement learning

edit

Reinforcement learning[213] gives an agent a reward every time it performs a desired action well, and may give negative rewards (or "punishments") when it performs poorly. It was described in the first half of the twentieth century by psychologists using animal models, such as Thorndike,[214][215] Pavlov[216] and Skinner.[217] In the 1950s, Alan Turing[215][218] and Arthur Samuel[215] foresaw the role of reinforcement learning in AI.

A successful and influential research program was led by Richard Sutton and Andrew Barto beginning 1972. Their collaboration revolutionized the study of reinforcement learning and decision making over the four decades.[219][220] In 1988, Sutton described machine learning in terms of decision theory (i.e., the Markov decision process). This gave the subject a solid theoretical foundation and access to a large body of theoretical results developed in the field of operations research.[220]

Also in 1988, Sutton and Barto developed the "temporal difference" (TD) learning algorithm, where the agent is rewarded only when its predictions about the future show improvement. It significantly outperformed previous algorithms.[221] TD-learning was used by Gerald Tesauro in 1992 in the program TD-Gammon, which played backgammon as well as the best human players. The program learned the game by playing against itself with zero prior knowledge.[222] In an interesting case of interdisciplinary convergence, neurologists discovered in 1997 that the dopamine reward system in brains also uses a version of the TD-learning algorithm.[223][224][225] TD learning would be become highly influential in the 21st century, used in both AlphaGo and AlphaZero.[226]

Second AI winter

edit

The business community's fascination with AI rose and fell in the 1980s in the classic pattern of an economic bubble. As dozens of companies failed, the perception in the business world was that the technology was not viable.[227] The damage to AI's reputation would last into the 21st century. Inside the field there was little agreement on the reasons for AI's failure to fulfill the dream of human level intelligence that had captured the imagination of the world in the 1960s. Together, all these factors helped to fragment AI into competing subfields focused on particular problems or approaches, sometimes even under new names that disguised the tarnished pedigree of "artificial intelligence".[228]

Over the next 20 years, AI consistently delivered working solutions to specific isolated problems. By the late 1990s, it was being used throughout the technology industry, although somewhat behind the scenes. The success was due to increasing computer power, by collaboration with other fields (such as mathematical optimization and statistics) and using the highest standards of scientific accountability. By 2000, AI had achieved some of its oldest goals. The field was both more cautious and more successful than it had ever been.

AI winter

edit

The term "AI winter" was coined by researchers who had survived the funding cuts of 1974 when they became concerned that enthusiasm for expert systems had spiraled out of control and that disappointment would certainly follow.[ae] Their fears were well founded: in the late 1980s and early 1990s, AI suffered a series of financial setbacks.[122]

The first indication of a change in weather was the sudden collapse of the market for specialized AI hardware in 1987. Desktop computers from Apple and IBM had been steadily gaining speed and power and in 1987 they became more powerful than the more expensive Lisp machines made by Symbolics and others. There was no longer a good reason to buy them. An entire industry worth half a billion dollars was demolished overnight.[230]

Eventually the earliest successful expert systems, such as XCON, proved too expensive to maintain. They were difficult to update, they could not learn, and they were "brittle" (i.e., they could make grotesque mistakes when given unusual inputs). Expert systems proved useful, but only in a few special contexts.[231]

In the late 1980s, the Strategic Computing Initiative cut funding to AI "deeply and brutally". New leadership at DARPA had decided that AI was not "the next wave" and directed funds towards projects that seemed more likely to produce immediate results.[232]

By 1991, the impressive list of goals penned in 1981 for Japan's Fifth Generation Project had not been met. Indeed, some of them, like "carry on a casual conversation" would not be accomplished for another 40 years. As with other AI projects, expectations had run much higher than what was actually possible.[233][af]

Over 300 AI companies had shut down, gone bankrupt, or been acquired by the end of 1993, effectively ending the first commercial wave of AI.[235] In 1994, HP Newquist stated in The Brain Makers that "The immediate future of artificial intelligence—in its commercial form—seems to rest in part on the continued success of neural networks."[235]

AI behind the scenes

edit

In the 1990s, algorithms originally developed by AI researchers began to appear as parts of larger systems. AI had solved a lot of very difficult problems[ag] and their solutions proved to be useful throughout the technology industry,[236][237] such as data mining, industrial robotics, logistics, speech recognition,[238] banking software,[239] medical diagnosis[239] and Google's search engine.[240][241]

The field of AI received little or no credit for these successes in the 1990s and early 2000s. Many of AI's greatest innovations have been reduced to the status of just another item in the tool chest of computer science.[242] Nick Bostrom explains: "A lot of cutting edge AI has filtered into general applications, often without being called AI because once something becomes useful enough and common enough it's not labeled AI anymore."[239]

Many researchers in AI in the 1990s deliberately called their work by other names, such as informatics, knowledge-based systems, "cognitive systems" or computational intelligence. In part, this may have been because they considered their field to be fundamentally different from AI, but also the new names help to procure funding.[238][243][244] In the commercial world at least, the failed promises of the AI Winter continued to haunt AI research into the 2000s, as the New York Times reported in 2005: "Computer scientists and software engineers avoided the term artificial intelligence for fear of being viewed as wild-eyed dreamers."[245]

Mathematical rigor, greater collaboration and a narrow focus

edit

AI researchers began to develop and use sophisticated mathematical tools more than they ever had in the past.[246][247] Most of the new directions in AI relied heavily on mathematical models, including artificial neural networks, probabilistic reasoning, soft computing and reinforcement learning. In the 90s and 2000s, many other highly mathematical tools were adapted for AI. These tools were applied to machine learning, perception and mobility.

There was a widespread realization that many of the problems that AI needed to solve were already being worked on by researchers in fields like statistics, mathematics, electrical engineering, economics or operations research. The shared mathematical language allowed both a higher level of collaboration with more established and successful fields and the achievement of results which were measurable and provable; AI had become a more rigorous "scientific" discipline.

Another key reason for the success in the 90s was that AI researchers focussed on specific problems with verifiable solutions (an approach later derided as narrow AI). This provided useful tools in the present, rather than speculation about the future.

Intelligent agents

edit

A new paradigm called "intelligent agents" became widely accepted during the 1990s.[248][249][ah] Although earlier researchers had proposed modular "divide and conquer" approaches to AI,[ai] the intelligent agent did not reach its modern form until Judea Pearl, Allen Newell, Leslie P. Kaelbling, and others brought concepts from decision theory and economics into the study of AI.[250] When the economist's definition of a rational agent was married to computer science's definition of an object or module, the intelligent agent paradigm was complete.

An intelligent agent is a system that perceives its environment and takes actions which maximize its chances of success. By this definition, simple programs that solve specific problems are "intelligent agents", as are human beings and organizations of human beings, such as firms. The intelligent agent paradigm defines AI research as "the study of intelligent agents".[aj] This is a generalization of some earlier definitions of AI: it goes beyond studying human intelligence; it studies all kinds of intelligence.

The paradigm gave researchers license to study isolated problems and to disagree about methods, but still retain hope that their work could be combined into an agent architecture that would be capable of general intelligence.[251]

Milestones and Moore's law

edit

On May 11, 1997, Deep Blue became the first computer chess-playing system to beat a reigning world chess champion, Garry Kasparov.[252] In 2005, a Stanford robot won the DARPA Grand Challenge by driving autonomously for 131 miles along an unrehearsed desert trail. Two years later, a team from CMU won the DARPA Urban Challenge by autonomously navigating 55 miles in an urban environment while responding to traffic hazards and adhering to traffic laws.[253]

These successes were not due to some revolutionary new paradigm, but mostly on the tedious application of engineering skill and on the tremendous increase in the speed and capacity of computers by the 90s.[ak] In fact, Deep Blue's computer was 10 million times faster than the Ferranti Mark 1 that Christopher Strachey taught to play chess in 1951.[al] This dramatic increase is measured by Moore's law, which predicts that the speed and memory capacity of computers doubles every two years. The fundamental problem of "raw computer power" was slowly being overcome.

Big data, deep learning, AGI (2005–2017)

edit

In the first decades of the 21st century, access to large amounts of data (known as "big data"), cheaper and faster computers and advanced machine learning techniques were successfully applied to many problems throughout the economy. A turning point was the success of deep learning around 2012 which improved the performance of machine learning on many tasks, including image and video processing, text analysis, and speech recognition.[255] Investment in AI increased along with its capabilities, and by 2016, the market for AI-related products, hardware, and software reached more than $8 billion, and the New York Times reported that interest in AI had reached a "frenzy".[256]

In 2002, Ben Goertzel and others became concerned that AI had largely abandoned its original goal of producing versatile, fully intelligent machines, and argued in favor of more direct research into artificial general intelligence. By the mid-2010s several companies and institutions had been founded to pursue Artificial General Intelligence (AGI), such as OpenAI and Google's DeepMind. During the same period, new insights into superintelligence raised concerns that AI was an existential threat. The risks and unintended consequences of AI technology became an area of serious academic research after 2016.

Big data and big machines

edit

The success of machine learning in the 2000s depended on the availability of vast amounts of training data and faster computers.[257] Russell and Norvig wrote that the "improvement in performance obtained by increasing the size of the data set by two or three orders of magnitude outweighs any improvement that can be made by tweaking the algorithm."[200] Geoffrey Hinton recalled that back in the 90s, the problem was that "our labeled datasets were thousands of times too small. [And] our computers were millions of times too slow."[258] This was no longer true by 2010.

The most useful data in the 2000s came from curated, labeled data sets created specifically for machine learning and AI. In 2007, a group at UMass Amherst released Labeled Faces in the Wild, an annotated set of images of faces that was widely used to train and test face recognition systems for the next several decades.[259] Fei-Fei Li developed ImageNet, a database of three million images captioned by volunteers using the Amazon Mechanical Turk. Released in 2009, it was a useful body of training data and a benchmark for testing for the next generation of image processing systems.[260][200] Google released word2vec in 2013 as an open source resource. It used large amounts of data text scraped from the internet and word embedding to create a numeric vector to represent each word. Users were surprised at how well it was able to capture word meanings, for example, ordinary vector addition would give equivalences like China + River = Yangtze, London+England-France = Paris.[261] This database in particular would be essential for the development of large language models in the late 2010s.

The explosive growth of the internet gave machine learning programs access to billions of pages of text and images that could be scraped. And, for specific problems, large privately held databases contained the relevant data. McKinsey Global Institute reported that "by 2009, nearly all sectors in the US economy had at least an average of 200 terabytes of stored data".[262] This collection of information was known in the 2000s as big data.

In a Jeopardy! exhibition match in February 2011, IBM's question answering system Watson defeated the two best Jeopardy! champions, Brad Rutter and Ken Jennings, by a significant margin.[263] Watson's expertise would have been impossible without the information available on the internet.[200]

Deep learning

edit

In 2012, AlexNet, a deep learning model,[am] developed by Alex Krizhevsky, won the ImageNet Large Scale Visual Recognition Challenge, with significantly fewer errors than the second place winner.[265][200] Krizhevsky worked with Geoffrey Hinton at the University of Toronto.[an] This was a turning point in machine learning: over the next few years dozens of other approaches to image recognition were abandoned in favor of deep learning.[257]

Deep learning uses a multi-layer perceptron. Although this architecture has been known since the 60s, getting it to work requires powerful hardware and large amounts of training data.[266] Before these became available, improving performance of image processing systems required hand-crafted ad hoc features that were difficult to implement.[266] Deep learning was simpler and more general.[ao]

Deep learning was applied to dozens of problems over the next few years (such as speech recognition, machine translation, medical diagnosis, and game playing). In every case it showed enormous gains in performance.[257] Investment and interest in AI boomed as a result.[257]

The alignment problem

edit

It became fashionable in the 2000s to begin talking about the future of AI again and several popular books considered the possibility of superintelligent machines and what they might mean for human society. Some of this was optimistic (such as Ray Kurzweil's The Singularity is Near), but others warned that a sufficiently powerful AI was existential threat to humanity, such as Nick Bostrom and Eliezer Yudkowsky.[267] The topic became widely covered in the press and many leading intellectuals and politicians commented on the issue.

AI programs in the 21st century are defined by their goals – the specific measures that they are designed to optimize. Nick Bostrom's influential 2005 book Superintelligence argued that, if one isn't careful about defining these goals, the machine may cause harm to humanity in the process of achieving a goal. Stuart J. Russell used the example of an intelligent robot that kills its owner to prevent it from being unplugged, reasoning "you can't fetch the coffee if you're dead".[268] (This problem is known by the technical term "instrumental convergence".) The solution is to align the machine's goal function with the goals of its owner and humanity in general. Thus, the problem of mitigating the risks and unintended consequences of AI became known as "the value alignment problem" or AI alignment.[269]

At the same time, machine learning systems had begun to have disturbing unintended consequences. Cathy O'Neil explained how statistical algorithms had been among the causes of the 2008 economic crash,[270] Julia Angwin of ProPublica argued that the COMPAS system used by the criminal justice system exhibited racial bias under some measures,[271][ap] others showed that many machine learning systems exhibited some form of racial bias,[273] and there were many other examples of dangerous outcomes that had resulted from machine learning systems.[aq]

In 2016, the election of Donald Trump and the controversy over the COMPAS system illuminated several problems with the current technological infrastructure, including misinformation, social media algorithms designed to maximize engagement, the misuse of personal data and the trustworthiness of predictive models.[274] Issues of fairness and unintended consequences became significantly more popular at AI conferences, publications vastly increased, funding became available, and many researchers re-focussed their careers on these issues. The value alignment problem became a serious field of academic study.[275][ar]

Artificial general intelligence research

edit

In the early 2000s, several researchers became concerned that mainstream AI was too focused on "measurable performance in specific applications"[277] (known as "narrow AI") and had abandoned AI's original goal of creating versatile, fully intelligent machines. An early critic was Nils Nilsson in 1995, and similar opinions were published by AI elder statesmen John McCarthy, Marvin Minsky, and Patrick Winston in 2007-2009. Minsky organized a symposium on "human-level AI" in 2004.[277] Ben Goertzel adopted the term "artificial general intelligence" for the new sub-field, founding a journal and holding conferences beginning in 2008.[278] The new field grew rapidly, buoyed by the continuing success of artificial neural networks and the hope that it was the key to AGI.

Several competing companies, laboratories and foundations were founded to develop AGI in the 2010s. DeepMind was founded in 2010 by three English scientists, Demis Hassabis, Shane Legg and Mustafa Suleyman, with funding from Peter Thiel and later Elon Musk. The founders and financiers were deeply concerned about AI safety and the existential risk of AI. DeepMind's founders had a personal connection with Yudkowsky and Musk was among those who was actively raising the alarm.[279] Hassabis was both worried about the dangers of AGI and optimistic about its power; he hoped they could "solve AI, then solve everything else."[280]

In 2012, Geoffrey Hinton (who been leading neural network research since the 80s) was approached by Baidu, which wanted to hire him and all his students for an enormous sum. Hinton decided to hold an auction and, at a Lake Tahoe AI conference, they sold themselves to Google for a price of $44 million. Hassabis took notice and sold DeepMind to Google in 2014, on the condition that it would not accept military contracts and would be overseen by an ethics board.[279]

Larry Page of Google, unlike Musk and Hassabis, was an optimist about the future of AI. Musk and Paige became embroiled in an argument about the risk of AGI at Musk's 2015 birthday party. They had been friends for decades but stopped speaking to each other shortly afterwards. Musk attended the one and only meeting of the DeepMind's ethics board, where it became clear that Google was uninterested in mitigating the harm of AGI. Frustrated by his lack of influence he founded OpenAI in 2015, enlisting Sam Altman to run it and hiring top scientists. OpenAI began as a non-profit, "free from the economic incentives that were driving Google and other corporations."[279] Musk became frustrated again and left the company in 2018. OpenAI turned to Microsoft for continued financial support and Altman and OpenAI formed a for-profit version of the company with more than $1 billion in financing.[279]

In 2021, Dario Amodei and 14 other scientists left OpenAI over concerns that the company was putting profits above safety. They formed Anthropic, which soon had $6 billion in financing from Microsoft and Google.[279]

The New York Times wrote in 2023 "At the heart of this competition is a brain-stretching paradox. The people who say they are most worried about AI are among the most determined to create it and enjoy its riches. They have justified their ambition with their strong belief that they alone can keep AI from endangering Earth."[279]

Large language models, AI boom (2020–present)

edit

The AI boom started with the initial development of key architectures and algorithms such as the transformer architecture in 2017, leading to the scaling and development of large language models exhibiting human-like traits of knowledge, attention and creativity. The new AI era began around 2020–2023, with the public release of scaled large language models (LLMs) such as ChatGPT.[281]

Transformer architecture and large language models

edit

In 2017, the transformer architecture was proposed by Google researchers. It exploits an attention mechanism and became widely used in large language models.[282]

Large language models, based on the transformer, were developed by AGI companies: OpenAI released GPT-3 in 2020, and DeepMind released Gato in 2022. These are foundation models: they are trained on vast quantities of unlabeled data and can be adapted to a wide range of downstream tasks.[citation needed]

These models can discuss a huge number of topics and display general knowledge. The question naturally arises: are these models an example of artificial general intelligence? Bill Gates was skeptical of the new technology and the hype that surrounded AGI. However, Altman presented him with a live demo of ChatGPT4 passing an advanced biology test. Gates was convinced.[279] In 2023, Microsoft Research tested the model with a large variety of tasks, and concluded that "it could reasonably be viewed as an early (yet still incomplete) version of an artificial general intelligence (AGI) system".[283]

Neurosymbolic AI

edit

DeepMind describes their approach as "neurosymbolic" because they use deep learning in combination with symbolic techniques. For example, AlphaZero uses deep learning to evaluate the strength of a position and to suggest policies (courses of action), but it uses Monte Carlo tree search to lookahead at new positions.[citation needed]

AI boom

edit

Investment in AI grew exponentially in after 2020.[citation needed]

By Mid-2024 several financial began to question the capacity of AI companies to produce a return on investment. Some observers[who?] speculated that AI was experiencing another bubble.[citation needed]

2024 Nobel Prizes

edit

In 2024, the Royal Swedish Academy of Sciences awarded Nobel Prizes in recognition of groundbreaking contributions to artificial intelligence. The recipients included:

  • In physics: John Hopfield for his work on physics-inspired Hopfield networks, and Geoffrey Hinton for foundational contributions to Boltzmann machines and deep learning.
  • In chemistry: David Baker, Demis Hassabis, and John Jumper for their advancements in protein folding predictions. See AlphaFold.

See also

edit

Notes

edit
  1. ^ The Lambda calculus was especially important to AI, since it was an inspiration for Lisp (the most important programming language used in 20th century AI).[46]
  2. ^ Alan Turing was thinking about machine intelligence at least as early as 1941, when he circulated a paper on machine intelligence which could be the earliest paper in the field of AI — although it is now lost. His 1950 paper was followed by three radio broadcasts on AI by Turing, the two lectures 'Intelligent Machinery, A Heretical Theory' and 'Can Digital Computers Think?' and the panel discussion 'Can Automatic Calculating Machines be Said to Think?'[60]
  3. ^ This was an early statement of the philosophical position John Searle would later call the "Strong AI hypothesis": that machines can contain minds just as human bodies do.
  4. ^ Daniel Crevier wrote "[the proposal] later became known as the 'physical symbol systems hypothesis'".[78] The physical symbol system hypothesis was articulated and named by Newell and Simon in their paper on GPS.[79] It includes a more specific definition of a "machine" as an agent that manipulates symbols.
  5. ^ "I won't swear and I hadn't seen it before," McCarthy told Pamela McCorduck in 1979.[80] However, McCarthy also stated unequivocally "I came up with the term" in a CNET interview.[81] The term was chosen by McCarthy to avoid associations with cybernetics and the influence of Norbert Wiener. "[O]ne of the reasons for inventing the term "artificial intelligence" was to escape association with "cybernetics". Its concentration on analog feedback seemed misguided, and I wished to avoid having either to accept Norbert (not Robert) Wiener as a guru or having to argue with him.".[82]
  6. ^ Pamela McCorduck discusses how the Dartmouth conference alumni dominated the first two decades of AI research, calling them the "invisible college".[83]
  7. ^ Daniel Crevier wrote "the conference is generally recognized as the official birthdate of the new science."[85]
  8. ^ There were a few psychologists who avoided behaviorism and embraced a cognitive approach before it was fashionable, such as Frederic Bartlett and Kenneth Craig[87]
  9. ^ Russell and Norvig wrote "it was astonishing whenever a computer did anything remotely clever." [88] AI founder John McCarthy called this the "Look, Ma, no hands!" era.[89]
  10. ^ This avoided the commonsense knowledge problem, discussed below.
  11. ^ The hardware diversity was particularly clear in the different technologies used in implementing the adjustable weights. The perceptron machines and the SNARC used potentiometers moved by electric motors. ADALINE used memistors adjusted by electroplating, though they also used simulations on an IBM 1620 computer. The MINOS machines used ferrite cores with multiple holes in them that could be individually blocked, with the degree of blockage representing the weights.[118]
  12. ^ Minsky strongly believes he was misquoted.[128][129]
  13. ^ McCorduck also notes that funding was mostly under the direction of alumni of the Dartmouth workshop of 1956.[134]
  14. ^ Russell and Norvig wrote "in almost all cases, these early systems failed on more difficult tasks."[143]
  15. ^ Bruce Buchanan wrote: "Early programs were necessarily limited in scope by the size and speed of memory"[145]
  16. ^ History would prove Moravec right about applications like computer vision. Moravec estimated that simply matching the edge and motion detection capabilities of the human retina in real time would require a general-purpose computer capable of 1000 million instructions per second (MIPS). In 1976, the fastest supercomputer, the $8 million Cray-1 was only capable of 130 MIPS, and a typical desktop computer had 1 MIPS. As of 2011, practical computer vision applications require 10,000 to 1,000,000 MIPS.[148]
  17. ^ Such as the frame, ramification and qualification problems, as well as the difficulty of default reasoning and word-sense disambiguation.
  18. ^ Russell and Norvig write: "[M]any of the concepts we name in language fail, on closer inspection, to have the logically defined necessary and sufficient conditions that early AI researchers hoped to capture in axiomatic form."[122]
  19. ^ John McCarthy wrote in response that "the combinatorial explosion problem has been recognized in AI from the beginning"[156]
  20. ^ This account is based on Crevier 1993, pp. 115–116. Other views include McCorduck 2004, pp. 306–313 and NRC 1999 under "Success in Speech Recognition".
  21. ^ Moravec explains, "Their initial promises to DARPA had been much too optimistic. Of course, what they delivered stopped considerably short of that. But they felt they couldn't in their next proposal promise less than in the first one, so they promised more."[158]
  22. ^ While the autonomous tank was a failure, the battle management system (called "DART") proved to be enormously successful, saving billions in the first Gulf War, repaying the investment and justifying the DARPA's pragmatic policy, at least as far as DARPA was concerned.[160]
  23. ^ "Know-how" is Dreyfus' term. Dreyfus makes a distinction between "knowing how" and "knowing that", a modern version of Heidegger's distinction of ready-to-hand and present-at-hand.[162]
  24. ^ Weizenbaum said: "I became the only member of the AI community to be seen eating lunch with Dreyfus. And I deliberately made it plain that theirs was not the way to treat a human being."[167]
  25. ^ Colby and his colleagues later also developed chatterbot-like "computer simulations of paranoid processes (PARRY)" to "make intelligible paranoid processes in explicit symbol processing terms."[171]
  26. ^ Wason & Shapiro (1966) showed that people do poorly on completely abstract problems, but if the problem is restated to allow the use of intuitive social intelligence, performance dramatically improves. (See Wason selection task) Kahneman, Slovic & Tversky (1982) have shown that people are terrible at elementary problems that involve uncertain reasoning. (See list of cognitive biases for several examples). Eleanor Rosch's work is described in Lakoff 1987. Kahnmann published a more general theory of symbolic cognition and other kinds of thinking in his book Thinking Fast and Slow (2011)
  27. ^ An early example of McCarthy's position was in the journal Science where he said "This is AI, so we don't care if it's psychologically real" (Kolata 1982), and he recently reiterated his position at the AI@50 conference where he said "Artificial intelligence is not, by definition, simulation of human intelligence" (Maker 2006).
  28. ^ Another aspect of the conflict was called "the procedural/declarative distinction" but did not prove to be influential in later AI research.
  29. ^ Versions of backpropagation had been developed in several fields, most directly as the reverse mode of automatic differentiation published by Seppo Linnainmaa (1970). It was applied to neural networks in the 1970s by Paul Werbos.[121]
  30. ^ Hans Moravec wrote: "I am confident that this bottom-up route to artificial intelligence will one date meet the traditional top-down route more than half way, ready to provide the real world competence and the commonsense knowledge that has been so frustratingly elusive in reasoning programs. Fully intelligent machines will result when the metaphorical golden spike is driven uniting the two efforts."[203]
  31. ^ AI winter was first used as the title of a seminar on the subject for the Association for the Advancement of Artificial Intelligence.[229]
  32. ^ McCorduck writes "Two and a half decades later, we can see that the Japanese didn't quite meet all of those ambitious goals."[234]
  33. ^ See Applications of artificial intelligence § Computer science
  34. ^ Russell and Norvig wrote "The whole-agent view is now widely accepted" [250]
  35. ^ Carl Hewitt's Actor model anticipated the modern definition of intelligent agents. (Hewitt, Bishop & Steiger 1973) Both John Doyle (Doyle 1983) and Marvin Minsky's popular classic The Society of Mind (Minsky 1986) used the word "agent". Other "modular" proposals included Rodney Brook's subsumption architecture, object-oriented programming and others.
  36. ^ This is how the most widely used textbooks of the 21st century define artificial intelligence, such as Russell and Norvig, 2021; Padgham and Winikoff, 2004; Jones, 2007; Poole and Mackworth, 2017.[250]
  37. ^ Ray Kurzweil wrote that the improvement in computer chess "is governed only by the brute force expansion of computer hardware."[254]
  38. ^ Cycle time of Ferranti Mark 1 was 1.2 milliseconds, which is arguably equivalent to about 833 flops. Deep Blue ran at 11.38 gigaflops (and this does not even take into account Deep Blue's special-purpose hardware for chess). Very approximately, these differ by a factor of 107.[citation needed]
  39. ^ AlexNet had 650,000 neurons and trained using ImageNet, augmented with reversed, cropped and tinted images. The model also used Geoffrey Hinton's dropout technique and a rectified linear output function, both relatively new developments at the time.[264]
  40. ^ Several other laboratories had developed systems that, like AlexNet, used GPU chips and performed nearly as well as AlexNet,[121] but AlexNet proved to be the most influential.
  41. ^ See History of AI § The problems above, where Hans Moravec predicted that raw power would eventually make AI "easy".
  42. ^ Later research showed that there was no way for system to avoid a measurable racist bias -- fixing one form of bias would necessarily introduce another.[272]
  43. ^ A short summary of topics would include privacy, surveillance, copyright, misinformation and deep fakes, filter bubbles and partisanship, algorithmic bias, misleading results that go undetected without algorithmic transparency, the right to an explanation, misuse of autonomous weapons and technological unemployment. See Artificial intelligence § Ethics
  44. ^ Brian Christian wrote "ProPublica's study [of COMPAS in 2015] legitimated concepts like fairness as valid topics for research"[276]
  1. ^ Kaplan & Haenlein 2018.
  2. ^ Newquist 1994, pp. 143–156.
  3. ^ Newquist 1994, pp. 144–152.
  4. ^ Rhodios 2007, Book 4, the Talos episode.
  5. ^ Bibliotheke 1.9.26
  6. ^ Rhodios 2007.
  7. ^ Morford 2007.
  8. ^ Linden 2003.
  9. ^ Kressel 2015.
  10. ^ Jewish Encyclopedia, GOLEM.
  11. ^ Newquist 1994, p. 38.
  12. ^ Talmud, Sanhedrin 65b.
  13. ^ O'Connor 1994.
  14. ^ Goethe 1890.
  15. ^ McCorduck 2004, pp. 17–25.
  16. ^ Butler 1863.
  17. ^ Newquist 1994, p. 65.
  18. ^ Cave & Dihal 2019.
  19. ^ Needham 1986, p. 53.
  20. ^ McCorduck 2004, p. 6.
  21. ^ Nick 2005.
  22. ^ McCorduck 2004, p. 10.
  23. ^ Newquist 1994, p. 40.
  24. ^ McCorduck 2004, p. 16.
  25. ^ McCorduck 2004, pp. 59–62.
  26. ^ McCorduck 2004, p. 17.
  27. ^ Levitt 2000.
  28. ^ Newquist 1994, p. 30.
  29. ^ Crevier 1993, p. 1.
  30. ^ Quoted in McCorduck 2004, p. 8.
  31. ^ Cave, Dihal & Dillon 2020, p. 56.
  32. ^ Butler 1948.
  33. ^ Porterfield 2006, p. 136.
  34. ^ Hollander 1964.
  35. ^ Russell & Norvig 2021, pp. 6 & 7.
  36. ^ a b Berlinski 2000.
  37. ^ Carreras y Artau 1939.
  38. ^ a b Russell & Norvig 2021, p. 6.
  39. ^ Bonner 2007.
  40. ^ Bonner 1985, pp. 57–71.
  41. ^ 17th century mechanism and AI:
  42. ^ Hobbes and AI:
  43. ^ Leibniz and AI:
  44. ^ Russell & Norvig 2021, p. 8.
  45. ^ a b c Russell & Norvig 2021, p. 9.
  46. ^ Crevier 1993, pp. 190 196, 61.
  47. ^ Rose 1946.
  48. ^ The Turing machine: and see
  49. ^ Couturat 1901.
  50. ^ a b Russell & Norvig 2021, p. 15.
  51. ^ Newquist 1994, p. 67.
  52. ^ Randall (1982, pp. 4–5); Byrne (2012); Mulvihill (2012)
  53. ^ Randall (1982, pp. 6, 11–13); Quevedo (1914); Quevedo (1915)
  54. ^ Randall 1982, pp. 13, 16–17.
  55. ^ Quoted in Russell & Norvig (2021, p. 15)
  56. ^ Menabrea & Lovelace 1843.
  57. ^ a b c Russell & Norvig 2021, p. 14.
  58. ^ McCorduck 2004, pp. 76–80.
  59. ^ AI's immediate predecessors:
  60. ^ a b c d Copeland 2004.
  61. ^ a b Dartmouth workshop:
  62. ^ Image adapted from Saygin 2000
  63. ^ Turing Test, Computing Machinery and Intelligence: See also
  64. ^ Newquist 1994, pp. 92–98.
  65. ^ Russell & Norvig 2021, p. 981.
  66. ^ Pitts & McCullough: See also: McCulloch & Pitts 1943
  67. ^ SNARC:
  68. ^ Turtles and Johns Hopkins Beast:
  69. ^ Russell & Norvig 2021, p. 17.
  70. ^ Copeland 1999.
  71. ^ Schaeffer 1997, Chapter 6.
  72. ^ Russell & Norvig 2021, p. 17, p=19.
  73. ^ McCorduck 2004, pp. 137–170.
  74. ^ Crevier 1993, pp. 44–47.
  75. ^ Logic Theorist:
  76. ^ Quoted in Crevier 1993, p. 46 and Russell & Norvig 2021, p. 18
  77. ^ McCarthy et al. 1955.
  78. ^ Crevier 1993, p. 48.
  79. ^ Newell & Simon 1963.
  80. ^ McCorduck 2004, p. 114.
  81. ^ Skillings 2006.
  82. ^ McCarthy 1996, p. 73.
  83. ^ a b McCorduck 2004, pp. 129–130.
  84. ^ McCorduck 2004, p. 125.
  85. ^ Crevier 1993, p. 49.
  86. ^ Miller 2003.
  87. ^ Russell & Norvig 2021, pp. 13–14.
  88. ^ Russell & Norvig 2003, p. 18.
  89. ^ a b Russell & Norvig 2021, p. 18.
  90. ^ Crevier 1993, pp. 52–107.
  91. ^ Moravec 1988, p. 9.
  92. ^ McCorduck 2004, p. 218; Newquist 1994, pp. 91–112; Crevier 1993, pp. 108–109
  93. ^ Crevier 1993, pp. 52–107; Moravec 1988, p. 9
  94. ^ State space search and problem solving:
  95. ^ McCorduck 2004, p. 246.
  96. ^ McCorduck 2004, pp. 245–250.
  97. ^ Russell & Norvig 2021, pp. 19, 106.
  98. ^ a b c Russell & Norvig 2021, p. 19.
  99. ^ Crevier 1993, pp. 51–58, 65–66.
  100. ^ Russell & Norvig 2021, p. 20.
  101. ^ STRIPS and Shakey:
  102. ^ McCorduck 2004, p. 286, Crevier 1993, pp. 76–79, Russell & Norvig 2021, p. 20
  103. ^ Crevier 1993, pp. 79–83.
  104. ^ Crevier 1993, pp. 164–172.
  105. ^ McCorduck 2004, pp. 291–296.
  106. ^ Crevier 1993, pp. 134–139.
  107. ^ a b Blocks world:
  108. ^ Perceptrons in the 60s:
  109. ^ Crevier 1993, p. 102.
  110. ^ Quoted in Crevier 1993, p. 102
  111. ^ Rosenblatt 1962.
  112. ^ Russell & Norvig 2021, pp. 20–21.
  113. ^ Widrow & Lehr 1990.
  114. ^ Rosen, Nilsson & Adams 1965.
  115. ^ Nilsson 1984.
  116. ^ Hart et al. 2003.
  117. ^ a b c Nielson 2005.
  118. ^ a b c d Olazaran Rodriguez 1991.
  119. ^ Minsky & Papert 1969.
  120. ^ a b c d Russell & Norvig 2021, p. 22.
  121. ^ a b c Schmidhuber 2022.
  122. ^ a b c d e f g h Russell & Norvig 2021, p. 24.
  123. ^ Crevier 1993, p. 105.
  124. ^ Simon & Newell 1958, pp. 7−8 quoted in Crevier 1993, p. 108.
  125. ^ Simon 1965, p. 96 quoted in Crevier 1993, p. 109
  126. ^ Minsky 1967, p. 2 quoted in Crevier 1993, p. 109
  127. ^ Darrach 1970.
  128. ^ McCorduck 2004, pp. 272–274.
  129. ^ Crevier 1993, p. 96.
  130. ^ Crevier 1993, pp. 64–65.
  131. ^ Crevier 1993, p. 94.
  132. ^ Howe 1994.
  133. ^ Crevier 1993, p. 51.
  134. ^ McCorduck 2004, p. 131.
  135. ^ Crevier 1993, p. 65.
  136. ^ Crevier 1993, pp. 68–71; Turkle 1984
  137. ^ Crevier 1993, pp. 163–196.
  138. ^ Dreyfus 1972.
  139. ^ a b c Lighthill 1973.
  140. ^ a b c d e Haigh 2023.
  141. ^ Crevier 1993, p. 143.
  142. ^ Nilsson 2009, p. 1.
  143. ^ a b c Russell & Norvig 2021, p. 21.
  144. ^ Crevier 1993, p. 146.
  145. ^ Buchanan 2005, p. 56.
  146. ^ Crevier 1993, pp. 146–148.
  147. ^ Moravec 1976.
  148. ^ Moravec 2000.
  149. ^ a b McCorduck 2004, p. 456.
  150. ^ a b Brooks 2002.
  151. ^ Moravec 1988, pp. 15–16.
  152. ^ Commonsense knowledge:
  153. ^ Quoted in Crevier 1993, p. 175
  154. ^ ALPAC:
  155. ^ Lighthill report:
  156. ^ McCarthy 1974.
  157. ^ Crevier 1993, pp. 115–116.
  158. ^ a b Crevier 1993, p. 115.
  159. ^ NRC 1999, under "Shift to Applied Research Increases Investment.".
  160. ^ NRC 1999.
  161. ^ Lucas and Penrose' critique of AI: Lucas original argument:
  162. ^ Dreyfus & Dreyfus 1986.
  163. ^ Dreyfus' critique of artificial intelligence: Dreyfus' version:
  164. ^ Searle's critique of AI: Searle's version:
  165. ^ Quoted in Crevier 1993, p. 143
  166. ^ Quoted in Crevier 1993, p. 122
  167. ^ Crevier 1993, p. 123.
  168. ^ Newquist 1994, p. 276.
  169. ^ Colby, Watt & Gilbert 1966, p. 148.
  170. ^ Weizenbaum 1976, pp. 5, 6.
  171. ^ Colby 1974, p. 6.
  172. ^ Weizenbaum's critique of AI: and see
  173. ^ a b McCorduck 2004, p. 51.
  174. ^ Crevier 1993, pp. 190–192.
  175. ^ Crevier 1993, pp. 193–196.
  176. ^ Crevier 1993, pp. 145–149, 258–63.
  177. ^ Neats vs. scruffies:
  178. ^ Frame (artificial intelligence): Minsky's frame paper:
  179. ^ Hayes 1981.
  180. ^ a b Reiter 1978.
  181. ^ Clark 1977.
  182. ^ Expert systems:
  183. ^ McCorduck 2004, pp. 327–335.
  184. ^ Crevier 1993, pp. 158–159.
  185. ^ Crevier 1993, p. 198.
  186. ^ Newquist 1994, p. 259.
  187. ^ Commercial expert systems:
  188. ^ Fifth generation computer:
  189. ^ Crevier 1993, p. 195.
  190. ^ a b Russell & Norvig 2021, p. 23.
  191. ^ Crevier 1993, p. 240.
  192. ^ McCorduck 2004, pp. 426–432.
  193. ^ NRC 1999, under "Shift to Applied Research Increases Investment".
  194. ^ McCorduck 2004, p. 299.
  195. ^ McCorduck 2004, p. 421.
  196. ^ Knowledge revolution:
  197. ^ Cyc and ontological engineering
  198. ^ Sejnowski 2018.
  199. ^ Crevier 1993, pp. 214–215.
  200. ^ a b c d e Russell & Norvig 2021, p. 26.
  201. ^ Christian 2020, pp. 21–22.
  202. ^ McCorduck 2004, pp. 454–462.
  203. ^ Moravec 1988, p. 20.
  204. ^ Crevier 1993, pp. 183–190.
  205. ^ Brooks 1990.
  206. ^ Brooks 1990, p. 3.
  207. ^ See, for example, Lakoff & Johnson 1999
  208. ^ Pollack 1984.
  209. ^ Pollack 1989.
  210. ^ Pearl 1988.
  211. ^ a b c Russell & Norvig 2021, p. 25.
  212. ^ Poole, Mackworth & Goebel 1998.
  213. ^ Russell & Norvig 2021, Section 23.
  214. ^ Christian 2020, pp. 120–124.
  215. ^ a b c Russell & Norvig 2021, p. 819.
  216. ^ Christian 2020, p. 124.
  217. ^ Christian 2020, pp. 152–156.
  218. ^ Christian 2020, p. 125.
  219. ^ Christian 2020, pp. 127–129.
  220. ^ a b Russell & Norvig 2021, pp. 25, 820.
  221. ^ Christian 2020, p. 140.
  222. ^ Christian 2020, p. 141.
  223. ^ Christian 2020, p. ?.
  224. ^ Russell & Norvig 2021, p. 820.
  225. ^ Schultz, Dayan & Montague 1997.
  226. ^ Russell & Norvig 2021, p. 822.
  227. ^ Newquist 1994, pp. 501, 511.
  228. ^ McCorduck 2004, p. 424.
  229. ^ Crevier 1993, p. 203.
  230. ^ Lisp machine crisis:
  231. ^ Expert systems failure (and the reason for it):
  232. ^ McCorduck 2004, pp. 430–431.
  233. ^ End of the Fifth generation computer initiative:
  234. ^ McCorduck 2004, p. 441.
  235. ^ a b Newquist 1994, p. 440.
  236. ^ NRC 1999, Artificial Intelligence in the 90s.
  237. ^ Kurzweil 2005, p. 264.
  238. ^ a b The Economist 2007.
  239. ^ a b c CNN 2006.
  240. ^ Olsen 2004.
  241. ^ Olsen 2006.
  242. ^ AI effect, AI behind the scenes in the 90s & 2000s:
  243. ^ Tascarella 2006.
  244. ^ Newquist 1994, p. 532.
  245. ^ Markoff 2005.
  246. ^ McCorduck 2004, pp. 486–487.
  247. ^ Russell & Norvig 2021, pp. 24–25.
  248. ^ McCorduck 2004, pp. 471–478.
  249. ^ Russell & Norvig 2021, chpt. 2.
  250. ^ a b c Russell & Norvig 2021, p. 61.
  251. ^ McCorduck 2004, p. 478.
  252. ^ McCorduck 2004, pp. 480–483.
  253. ^ Russell & Norvig 2021, p. 28.
  254. ^ Kurzweil 2005, p. 274.
  255. ^ LeCun, Bengio & Hinton 2015.
  256. ^ Lohr 2016.
  257. ^ a b c d Russell & Norvig 2021, pp. 26–27.
  258. ^ Quoted in Christian 2020, p. 22
  259. ^ Christian 2020, p. 31.
  260. ^ Christian 2020, pp. 22–23.
  261. ^ Christian 2020, p. 6.
  262. ^ McKinsey & Co 2011.
  263. ^ Markoff 2011.
  264. ^ Christian 2020, pp. 23–24.
  265. ^ Christian 2020, p. 24.
  266. ^ a b Russell & Norvig 2021, p. 27.
  267. ^ Russell & Norvig 2021, pp. 33, 1004.
  268. ^ Russell 2020.
  269. ^ Russell & Norvig 2021, pp. 5, 33, 1002–1003.
  270. ^ O'Neill 2016.
  271. ^ Christian 2020, pp. 60–61.
  272. ^ Christian 2020, pp. 67–70.
  273. ^ Christian 2020, pp. 6–7, 25.
  274. ^ Christian 2020, p. 67.
  275. ^ Christian 2020, pp. 67, 73, 117.
  276. ^ Christian 2020, p. 73.
  277. ^ a b Russell & Norvig 2021, p. 32.
  278. ^ Russell & Norvig 2021, p. 33.
  279. ^ a b c d e f g Metz et al. 2023.
  280. ^ Russell & Norvig 2021, p. 31.
  281. ^ AI boom:
  282. ^ Murgia 2023.
  283. ^ Bubeck et al. 2023.

References

edit



.