Well-ordering principle

In mathematics, the well-ordering principle states that every non-empty subset of nonnegative integers contains a least element.[1] In other words, the set of nonnegative integers is well-ordered by its "natural" or "magnitude" order in which precedes if and only if is either or the sum of and some nonnegative integer (other orderings include the ordering ; and ).

The phrase "well-ordering principle" is sometimes taken to be synonymous with the "well-ordering theorem". On other occasions it is understood to be the proposition that the set of integers contains a well-ordered subset, called the natural numbers, in which every nonempty subset contains a least element.

Properties

edit

Depending on the framework in which the natural numbers are introduced, this (second-order) property of the set of natural numbers is either an axiom or a provable theorem. For example:

  • In Peano arithmetic, second-order arithmetic and related systems, and indeed in most (not necessarily formal) mathematical treatments of the well-ordering principle, the principle is derived from the principle of mathematical induction, which is itself taken as basic.
  • Considering the natural numbers as a subset of the real numbers, and assuming that we know already that the real numbers are complete (again, either as an axiom or a theorem about the real number system), i.e., every bounded (from below) set has an infimum, then also every set   of natural numbers has an infimum, say  . We can now find an integer   such that   lies in the half-open interval  , and can then show that we must have  , and   in  .
  • In axiomatic set theory, the natural numbers are defined as the smallest inductive set (i.e., set containing 0 and closed under the successor operation). One can (even without invoking the regularity axiom) show that the set of all natural numbers   such that "  is well-ordered" is inductive, and must therefore contain all natural numbers; from this property one can conclude that the set of all natural numbers is also well-ordered.

In the second sense, this phrase is used when that proposition is relied on for the purpose of justifying proofs that take the following form: to prove that every natural number belongs to a specified set  , assume the contrary, which implies that the set of counterexamples is non-empty and thus contains a smallest counterexample. Then show that for any counterexample there is a still smaller counterexample, producing a contradiction. This mode of argument is the contrapositive of proof by complete induction. It is known light-heartedly as the "minimal criminal" method[citation needed] and is similar in its nature to Fermat's method of "infinite descent".

Garrett Birkhoff and Saunders Mac Lane wrote in A Survey of Modern Algebra that this property, like the least upper bound axiom for real numbers, is non-algebraic; i.e., it cannot be deduced from the algebraic properties of the integers (which form an ordered integral domain).

Example applications

edit

The well-ordering principle can be used in the following proofs.

Prime factorization

edit

Theorem: Every integer greater than one can be factored as a product of primes. This theorem constitutes part of the Prime Factorization Theorem.

Proof (by well-ordering principle). Let   be the set of all integers greater than one that cannot be factored as a product of primes. We show that   is empty.

Assume for the sake of contradiction that   is not empty. Then, by the well-ordering principle, there is a least element  ;   cannot be prime since a prime number itself is considered a length-one product of primes. By the definition of non-prime numbers,   has factors  , where   are integers greater than one and less than  . Since  , they are not in   as   is the smallest element of  . So,   can be factored as products of primes, where   and  , meaning that  , a product of primes. This contradicts the assumption that  , so the assumption that   is nonempty must be false.[2]

Integer summation

edit

Theorem:   for all positive integers  .

Proof. Suppose for the sake of contradiction that the above theorem is false. Then, there exists a non-empty set of positive integers  . By the well-ordering principle,   has a minimum element   such that when  , the equation is false, but true for all positive integers less than  . The equation is true for  , so  ;   is a positive integer less than  , so the equation holds for   as it is not in  . Therefore,   which shows that the equation holds for  , a contradiction. So, the equation must hold for all positive integers.[2]

References

edit
  1. ^ Apostol, Tom (1976). Introduction to Analytic Number Theory. New York: Springer-Verlag. pp. 13. ISBN 0-387-90163-9.
  2. ^ a b Lehman, Eric; Meyer, Albert R; Leighton, F Tom. Mathematics for Computer Science (PDF). Retrieved 2 May 2023.