Author | Karl Popper |
---|---|
Language | English |
Subject | Philosophy |
Publisher | Routledge |
Publication date | 1957 |
Publication place | United Kingdom |
The Poverty of Historicism, is a book by Karl Popper which seeks to persuade the reader of both the danger and the bankruptcy of the idea of Historicism.
Publication
edit"The Poverty of Historicism" was first written as a paper which was read in 1936, then updated and published as a book in 1957.[1] It is dedicated “In memory of the countless men and women of all creeds or nations or races who fell victim to the fascist and communist belief in Inexorable Laws of Historical Destiny.”
Synopsis
editPopper defines Historicism as: “an approach to the social sciences which assumes that historical prediction is their principal aim…”[2] . “The belief… that it is the task of the social sciences to lay bare the law of evolution of society in order to foretell its future… might be described as the central Historicist doctrine.”[3].
He distinguishes two main strands of Historicism, a “pro-naturalistic” approach which “favours the application of the methods of physics”[4], and the “anti-naturalistic” approach which opposes these methods.
The first two parts of the book set out Popper's definition of anti-naturalist and pro-naturalist Historicist views.
The second two parts of the book contain Popper's criticism of anti-naturalist and pro-naturalist Historicist views.
Popper concludes by contrasting the antiquity of Historicism (which, for example, Plato is said to have espoused) with the claims of modernity made by its twentieth century adherents.[5]
Popper's Criticisms of Historicism
editPopper’s criticisms of the poverty of the idea of historical prediction can broadly be split into three areas: (A) fundamental problems with the idea itself, (B) common inconsistencies in the arguments of Historicists, and (C) the negative practical effects of implementing Historicist ideas.
(A) Fundamental problems with Historicist theory
editi) A description of the whole of history of the whole of society is impossible because the list of characteristics making up such a description would be infinite. If we cannot know the whole of the present state of the mankind it follows that we cannot know the future of the mankind.
“If we wish to study a thing, we are bound to select certain aspects of it. It is not possible for us to observe or to describe a whole piece of the world, or a whole piece of nature; in fact, not even the smallest whole piece may be so described, since all description is necessarily selective.” [6]
ii) Human history is a single unique event. Knowledge of the past therefore does not necessarily help one to know the future. “The evolution of life on earth, or of human society, is a unique historical process… Its description, however, is not a law, but only a singular historical statement.” [7]
Study of history may reveal trends. However there is no guarantee that these trends will continue. In other words: they are not laws; “a statement asserting the existence of a trend at a certain time and place would be a singular historical statement and not a universal law.”[8]
In addition, given that historians are interested in the uniqueness of past events, it may be said that future events will possess a uniqueness cannot be known in advance.[9]
iii) Individual human action or reaction can never be predicted with certainty, therefore neither can the future: “the human factor is the ultimately uncertain and wayward element in social life and in all social institutions. Indeed this is the element which ultimately cannot be completely controlled by institutions (as Spinoza first saw); for every attempt at controlling it completely must lead to tyranny; which means, to the omnipotence of the human factor – the whims of a few men, or even one.”[10].
Popper asserts that psychology cannot lead to a complete understanding of “the human factor” because “’human nature’ varies considerably with the social institutions, and its study therefore presupposes an understanding of these institutions.”[11]
iv) A law, natural (i.e. scientific) or social, may enable us to exclude the possibility of certain events but it does not allow us to narrow down the range of possible outcomes to only one.[12] This follows from Popper’s theory of science: a hypothesis is proposed (it does not matter how the hypothesis was derived) and is then subjected to rigorous tests which aim to disprove the hypothesis. If no tests disprove the hypothesis it may become known as a law but in fact remains simply a so-far-unfalsified hypothesis.
Equally, examples of where theories are correct are useless in proving the validity of the theory.
v) It is logically impossible to know the future course of history when that course depends in part on the future growth of scientific knowledge (which is unknowable in advance).[13]
(B) Common inconsistencies in the arguments of Historicists
editi) Historicists often require the remodelling of man to become fit for the future society or hasten the arrival of this society. Given that society is composed of mankind, remaking man for a particular society can lead to any type of society. Also, a need to remodel man suggests that without this remodelling, the new society may not come about, and is therefore not inevitable.[14]
ii) Historicists are bad at imagining conditions under which an identified trend ceases. Historical generalisations may be reduced to a set of laws of higher generality (i.e. one could say that history depends upon psychology). However in order to form predictions from these generalisations we also need specific initial conditions. To the extent that conditions change or are changing, any ‘law’ may apply differently and trends may disappear.[15]
iii) Historicism tends to mistake historical interpretations for theories. When studying history we can only examine a limited aspect of the past. In other words we must apply a ‘historical interpretation’. It is necessary to appreciate a plurality of valid of interpretations (although some may be more fertile than others).[16]
v) Confusing ends with aims: Historicism tends to foster the idea that the aims of society are discernable in the trends of history, or what will inevitably come to pass becomes that which should come to pass. The aims of society may be more usefully thought as a matter of choice for that society.[17]
(C) Negative practical effects of implementing Historicist ideas
editi) Unintended consequences: the implementation of Historicist programs such as Marxism often means a fundamental change to society. Due to the complexity of social interaction this results in lots of unintended consequences (i.e. it tends not to work properly). Equally it becomes impossible to tease out the cause of any given effect so nothing is learnt from the experiment / revolution.[18]
ii) Lack of information: large scale social experiments cannot increase our knowledge of the social process because as power is centralised to enable theories to put into practice, dissent must be repressed, and so it is harder and harder to find out what people really think, and so whether the utopian experiment is working properly. This assumes that a dictator in such a position could be benevolent and not corrupted by the accumulation of power, which may be doubted.[19]
In addition, Popper rejects the notion that history cannot be subject to experiment[20] and that any ‘laws of history’ can only apply to a particular historical period.[21] Both of these ideas are treated as typical of the anti-naturalistic Historicist approaches by Popper.
The positive side to Historicism
editHowever Popper does concede that Historicism has an appeal as an antidote to the idea that history is shaped by the actions of ‘great men’.[22]
Popper's alternative to Historicism
editAs an alternative to Historicism Popper puts forward his own preference for “piecemeal social engineering” whereby small and reversible changes are made to society in order to be best able to learn from the changes made. The unpredictability of the future makes the effect of any larger changes random and untraceable. Small changes enable one to make limited, but testable and therefore falsifiable statements about the effect of social actions.[23]
Criticisms
editReferences
edit- ^ K Popper, The Poverty of Historicism, "Historical Note" prefacing the book
- ^ K Popper, The Poverty of Historicism, p. 3
- ^ K Popper, The Poverty of Historicism, p. 105-106
- ^ K Popper, The Poverty of Historicism, p. 2
- ^ K Popper, The Poverty of Historicism, section 33
- ^ K Popper, The Poverty of Historicism, section 23, p. 77
- ^ K Popper, The Poverty of Historicism, section 27, p. 108
- ^ K Popper, The Poverty of Historicism, section 27, p. 115
- ^ K Popper, The Poverty of Historicism, section 30
- ^ K Popper, The Poverty of Historicism, section 32, p. 158
- ^ K Popper, The Poverty of Historicism, section 32, p. 158
- ^ K Popper, The Poverty of Historicism, section 29
- ^ K Popper, The Poverty of Historicism, preface
- ^ K Popper, The Poverty of Historicism, section 21
- ^ K Popper, The Poverty of Historicism, section 28
- ^ K Popper, The Poverty of Historicism, section 31
- ^ K Popper, The Poverty of Historicism, section 22
- ^ K Popper, The Poverty of Historicism, section 21
- ^ K Popper, The Poverty of Historicism, section 24
- ^ K Popper, The Poverty of Historicism, section 25
- ^ K Popper, The Poverty of Historicism, section 26
- ^ K Popper, The Poverty of Historicism, section 31
- ^ K Popper, The Poverty of Historicism, sections 20-21
External links
edit