Killing baby Hitler is a thought experiment in ethics and theoretical physics which poses the question of using time travel to assassinate an infant Adolf Hitler. It presents an ethical dilemma in both the action and its consequences, as well as a temporal paradox in the logical consistency of time. Killing baby Hitler first became a literary trope of science fiction during World War II and has since been used to explore these ethical and metaphysical debates.

Adolf Hitler as an infant (c. 1889–1890)

Ethical debates on the problem of killing baby Hitler can demonstrate the outlook of various moral philosophies: utilitarianism holds that killing baby Hitler is justified, as the potential benefits outweigh the potential costs; deontology holds that killing baby Hitler is unjustified, as infanticide is always wrong; and consequentialism may question what the consequences of killing baby Hitler might be, holding that the unforeseen future consequences of such an act make it difficult to judge its morality. It is also used to raise the question of nature versus nurture, whether changing the society that baby Hitler grew up in might be preferable to killing baby Hitler.

Metaphysical debates about the possibility of killing baby Hitler have been used to discuss different philosophies of time: the B-theory of time considers killing baby Hitler to be impossible due to its inherent temporal paradox, while theories of multiple time dimensions leave room for the past to be changed by killing baby Hitler.

Public debate around the question of killing baby Hitler reached its height in late 2015, after The New York Times published a poll asking its readers the question. Advocates of killing baby Hitler included Florida governor Jeb Bush and film actor Tom Hanks, while comedian Stephen Colbert and pundit Ben Shapiro were counted among the opponents of the policy.

Ethical thought experiment

edit

Consequentialist argument

edit

According to consequentialism, the morality of any given action is judged solely by its consequences.[1] Consequentialist ethics raises the dichotomy of immediate foreseeable consequences versus unforeseeable potential consequences; for example, in the story of Johann Kühberger saving a young Hitler from drowning, the immediate positive consequences of saving a person's life was the motivating factor, but it also resulted in the eventual negative consequences of Hitler's rise to power.[2] In a 2000 essay on consequentialism, British philosopher James Lenman posited a German bandit in 100 BCE sparing the life of one of Hitler's distant ancestors. According to consequentialism, although the bandit sparing her life led to the unforeseeable future crimes of Hitler, he was not wrong to do so, as killing her could have led to even worse unforeseeable consequences.[3] Killing baby Hitler also raises the possibility of unforeseen consequences, including the commonly-cited possibility that someone even worse than Hitler could rise to power in his place.[4] As the consequences of killing baby Hitler are not known, the problem lacks a clear solution.[3]

Deontological argument

edit

According to deontology, the morality of an action is determined by certain ethical values, rather than by circumstances.[5] Even in the case that it would benefit the common good, deontology opposes killing out of the belief that all human beings have an "inalienable value".[6] Deontological ethics thus argues against killing baby Hitler, as it considers killing babies to always be wrong, irrespective of any potential consequences.[7]

Utilitarian argument

edit

Utilitarianism is a moral philosophy that argues for the maximisation of happiness and the minimisation of suffering.[8] According to utilitarian ethics, killing baby Hitler is justified,[9] as it considers the potential benefits to be greater than the moral cost.[7] As Hitler was responsible for the suffering of millions of people, utilitarianism posits that killing one baby Hitler is justifiable in order to save millions of innocent lives.[10] In this way, the question of killing baby Hitler resembles the trolley problem, which utilitarianism responds to similarly.[11] Arguments against the utilitarian response conclude that focusing on killing baby Hitler, without any guarantee of preventing future suffering, means that the only guaranteed outcome is that the time traveller would have committed the moral evil of infanticide.[12] American philosopher Janet Stemwedel therefore considers killing baby Hitler to be an unreliable means for maximising happiness. Stemwedel posits that applying utilitarian ethics to time travel favours causation over human agency, disregarding the capacity for humans to choose different paths and change.[8]

Nature versus nurture

edit

To Canadian psychologist Julia Shaw, the answer one gives to the baby Hitler question is telling of their view on nature versus nurture: people who would kill baby Hitler may have a deterministic view of individual predisposition towards evil, while people that would not kill baby Hitler may place higher value on environmental factors of upbringing and social conditions.[13] In a psychoanalysis of Hitler's infancy, Austrian psychiatrist Frederick Redlich found that he was "a fairly normal child" and showed few signs of the genocidal intent or dictatorial tendencies that would characterise his adulthood.[13] As there is no scientific explanation for Hitler's later actions based on his genetics, greater attention is often paid to Hitler's early childhood environment.[13] In a refutation of the great man theory,[14] it can be argued that killing baby Hitler would not eliminate this cultural environment, which would still result in other people growing up to pursue far-right politics and genocidal policies.[15] From this perspective, Janet Stemwedel argues that using time travel to change social conditions would be preferable to infanticide, as it would recognise that the responsibility for Hitler's actions lie not just with him, but also in the collective responsibility of those that raised, followed and elected him.[8]

Limitations

edit

The moral justification for killing baby Hitler usually rests on the question of whether a child can be held responsible for their future actions, before they had yet committed any crimes against humanity.[16] A follow-up question can then be posed regarding where the line ends for killing babies that would commit crimes against humanity.[17] The question of where the line ends was brought up by American activist Shaun King, who argued that the logic for killing baby Hitler could just as easily be applied to a newborn Christopher Columbus, infant slave-owners or a young Dylann Roof.[18] Australian moral philosopher Matthew Beard likewise brought up the idea of a baby Pol Pot and Joseph Stalin, arguing that a clear set of ethical principles would be needed to determine which historical babies deserve to be killed.[19]

In theoretical physics

edit

The question of killing baby Hitler contains a version of the grandfather paradox,[20] also known as the "Hitler's Murder Paradox".[21] According to the B-theory of time,[22] if someone travelled back in time with the intention of killing baby Hitler, then their reason for travelling back in time would be eliminated. It is often concluded that as the past has already happened, alteration of the past is a logical impossibility.[23] As Hitler killed himself in 1945, it can also be inferred that no time traveler has killed baby Hitler.[24]

In contrast to the B-theory, models that adopt the A-theory of time avoid logical contradictions in the killing of baby Hitler by considering time to be two-dimensional, where the first dimension is standard time (tx) and the second dimension is known as hyper-time (Htx).[25] Theories that leave room for the past to be changed include hyper-eternalism, two-dimensional presentism and hyper-presentism, which each demonstrate the possibility of killing baby Hitler in two-dimensional time.[26] In these temporal models, both the past and the future are held to be mutable; in changing the past by killing baby Hitler, the time traveller also changes the future.[27] Although it can also be debated whether such temporal models genuinely change the past, or if killing baby Hitler simply affects the past by causing a variation in hyper-time.[28]

If time travel caused creation of a parallel universe, killing baby Hitler would only create a parallel universe without Hitler in it, and the original universe would continue existing and thus the suffering he caused in that timeline would not be alleviated by the time-traveling assassin. From this perspective, astrophysicist Brian Koberlein concluded that killing baby Hitler would be "inconsequential at best, and could be downright harmful", recommending that time travelers avoid such an activity and instead visit the 1980s.[29]

Literary trope

edit

Killing baby Hitler is a common literary trope of contemporary science fiction,[30] usually depicting a time traveler going back to the 1890s to assassinate an infant Hitler before he can start World War II and perpetrate the Holocaust.[31] Stories of this kind date as far back as World War II itself, with publications in Weird Tales (1941)[32] and Astounding Science Fiction (1942) including the trope.[33]

Stories in the sub-genre detail a variety of different consequences for killing baby Hitler.[34] In his 1995 short story "Dieu porte-t-il des lunettes noires?", Maurice G. Dantec presents an ethical dilemma in travelling through time to kill baby Hitler.[35] In his 1996 novel Making History, Stephen Fry depicts a history student travelling back in time and rendering Alois Hitler infertile. But in the place of Adolf Hitler, a different and more effective Nazi dictator takes power, defeats the Soviet Union with nuclear weapons, conquers Europe and exterminates the Jewish people.[3] In Selden Edwards' 2008 novel The Little Book, the protagonists find themselves back in 1890s Vienna and decide to assassinate a young Hitler, but find themselves unable to kill an "innocent boy", despite knowing what he would grow up to become.[36] In a 2015 short story, American humourist Alexandra Petri depicted Hitler being abducted and raised well by a kindly time traveler.[37] In a post-credits scene of the 2018 film Deadpool 2, the titular character goes back in time to kill baby Hitler, but the outcome is not shown.[38] In the extended cut, the film shows Deadpool realising he can not do it and changing baby Hitler's diaper.[39]

In order to avoid the "Hitler-murder paradox", some science fiction stories follow the Novikov self-consistency principle, which holds that if time travel is possible, then changing the past cannot meaningfully alter the future. In the 1977 novella The Primal Solution, an elderly Holocaust survivor travels through time and attempts to kill a young Hitler, but he survives and is set down the path of antisemitism by the experience.[3] In a 2002 episode of The Twilight Zone, "Cradle of Darkness", a woman travels through time and kills baby Hitler,[1] but another baby is adopted by Hitler's mother and grows up to do all the same things as Hitler.[3] An earlier episode of The Twilight Zone, "No Time Like the Past" (1963), depicts a time traveler failing to assassinate Hitler, in keeping with the self-consistency principle.[40] In Juliusz Machulski's 2013 film AmbaSSada, the protagonists get transported back in time and meet Hitler due to a coincidence, only spontaneously deciding to kill him. As they had not travelled in time with the intention of killing Hitler, the "Hitler's Murder Paradox" is avoided and history is consequently altered.[21]

Public debate

edit

In conversations about time travel, it is common to raise the subject of changing the past and specifically the question of killing baby Hitler,[41] in what is also known as "Godwin's law of time travel".[29] Public debate on the baby Hitler question was brought to prominence in October 2015, when a poll by The New York Times asked its readers if they would kill baby Hitler.[3] The poll received a plurality of affirmative responses:[42] 42% said they would kill baby Hitler, 30% said they would not and 28% were undecided.[43] The poll caused the hashtag #babyhitler to begin trending on Twitter, as the social media platform's users debated the subject.[36]

During the campaign for the 2016 Republican Party presidential primaries, when the question of killing baby Hitler was posed by journalists of HuffPost to Florida governor Jeb Bush, he responded "Hell Yeah, I Would!".[44] While acknowledging the potential unknown consequences of such an action, he affirmed that he would still do it, saying "You gotta step up, man."[45] American engineer Paul J. Nahin commented that Bush had responded in this way in order to demonstrate "the toughness of his character", while pointing out that the Republican candidate also opposed abortion.[46] The issue of killing baby Hitler was also raised during that year's Democratic Party presidential primaries, with New Hampshire primary candidate Vermin Supreme making it one of the four planks of his political platform.[47] American actor Tom Hanks responded to the political debate by declaring that he would vote for a presidential candidate that supported killing baby Hitler.[48] When the question was posed to Microsoft's chatbot Tay, it likewise replied that "of course" it would kill baby Hitler.[49]

In contrast, American comedian Stephen Colbert responded to the question by saying that he would not kill baby Hitler and would instead seek to raise him in a loving home.[50] In a 2018 interview with The Washington Post, American actor John C. Reilly responded similarly, calling for empathy with baby Hitler as an apolitical alternative.[51] At the March for Life in 2019, American conservative pundit Ben Shapiro argued against killing baby Hitler from an anti-abortion position, stating that "Baby Hitler was a baby."[52] His comments drew criticism and mockery from liberal commentators.[53] In response to his position on killing baby Hitler, three companies pulled their advertisements from Shapiro's podcast.[54]

See also

edit

References

edit
  1. ^ a b Matthews 2019; Miltimore 2022.
  2. ^ Marks 2016, p. 72.
  3. ^ a b c d e f Matthews 2019.
  4. ^ Beard 2015; Ford 2015; Koberlein 2015; Matthews 2019; Stemwedel 2015.
  5. ^ Alper 2020, p. 3.
  6. ^ Strauss 2015.
  7. ^ a b Alper 2020, p. 3; Strauss 2015.
  8. ^ a b c Stemwedel 2015.
  9. ^ Alper 2020, p. 3; Matthews 2019; Stemwedel 2015; Strauss 2015.
  10. ^ Matthews 2019; Stemwedel 2015; Strauss 2015.
  11. ^ Ford 2015; Miltimore 2022; Strauss 2015.
  12. ^ Beard 2015; Stemwedel 2015.
  13. ^ a b c Shaw 2019.
  14. ^ Olasov 2020.
  15. ^ Beard 2015; Ford 2015; Olasov 2020; Stemwedel 2015.
  16. ^ Beard 2015; Febel, Knopf & Nonhoff 2023, p. 45; Strauss 2015.
  17. ^ Beard 2015; King 2016; Stemwedel 2015.
  18. ^ King 2016.
  19. ^ Beard 2015.
  20. ^ Febel, Knopf & Nonhoff 2023, p. 45; Grabias 2023, p. 480; Koberlein 2015; Matthews 2019; Rard 2019; Vihvelin 2020, p. 316.
  21. ^ a b Grabias 2023, p. 480.
  22. ^ Andreoletti & Spolaore 2021, pp. 10571–10572.
  23. ^ Andreoletti & Spolaore 2021, pp. 10571–10572; Goddu 2024, p. 5; Grabias 2023, p. 480; Kaiserman 2023, pp. 283–285; Koberlein 2015; Rard 2019; Vihvelin 1996, pp. 328–329.
  24. ^ Kaiserman 2023, pp. 283–285; Vihvelin 2020, pp. 316–317.
  25. ^ Andreoletti & Spolaore 2021, p. 10572.
  26. ^ Andreoletti & Spolaore 2021, pp. 10572–10573.
  27. ^ Andreoletti & Spolaore 2021, p. 10573.
  28. ^ Andreoletti & Spolaore 2021, p. 10573n1.
  29. ^ a b Koberlein 2015.
  30. ^ Febel, Knopf & Nonhoff 2023, p. 45; Koberlein 2015; Nahin 2017, p. 238.
  31. ^ Febel, Knopf & Nonhoff 2023, p. 45; Koberlein 2015.
  32. ^ Blevins 2016; Nahin 2017, pp. 238–239.
  33. ^ Nahin 2017, pp. 238–239.
  34. ^ Nahin 2017, p. 239.
  35. ^ Bragança 2019, p. 103n3.
  36. ^ a b Febel, Knopf & Nonhoff 2023, p. 45.
  37. ^ Petri 2015.
  38. ^ Crucchiola 2018; Hornshaw 2018.
  39. ^ Hornshaw 2018.
  40. ^ Rard 2019.
  41. ^ Blevins 2016; Kaiserman 2023, p. 283; Koberlein 2015.
  42. ^ Conroy & Strauss 2015.
  43. ^ Febel, Knopf & Nonhoff 2023, p. 45; King 2016; Miltimore 2022.
  44. ^ Beard 2015; Conroy & Strauss 2015; Kaplan 2016; Marks 2016, p. 72n38.
  45. ^ Beard 2015; Conroy & Strauss 2015.
  46. ^ Nahin 2017, p. 238.
  47. ^ Kaplan 2016.
  48. ^ Amanpour 2015.
  49. ^ Kantrowitz 2016.
  50. ^ Marks 2016, p. 72n38.
  51. ^ Jewell 2018.
  52. ^ Concha 2019; Fisher 2019; Matthews 2019; Miltimore 2022.
  53. ^ Concha 2019.
  54. ^ Fisher 2019.

Bibliography

edit

Book chapters

edit

Journal articles

edit

News articles

edit

Further reading

edit
edit