In mathematics, especially in order theory, the cofinality cf(A) of a partially ordered set A is the least of the cardinalities of the cofinal subsets of A.
This definition of cofinality relies on the axiom of choice, as it uses the fact that every non-empty set of cardinal numbers has a least member. The cofinality of a partially ordered set A can alternatively be defined as the least ordinal x such that there is a function from x to A with cofinal image. This second definition makes sense without the axiom of choice. If the axiom of choice is assumed, as will be the case in the rest of this article, then the two definitions are equivalent.
Cofinality can be similarly defined for a directed set and is used to generalize the notion of a subsequence in a net.
Examples
edit- The cofinality of a partially ordered set with greatest element is 1 as the set consisting only of the greatest element is cofinal (and must be contained in every other cofinal subset).
- In particular, the cofinality of any nonzero finite ordinal, or indeed any finite directed set, is 1, since such sets have a greatest element.
- Every cofinal subset of a partially ordered set must contain all maximal elements of that set. Thus the cofinality of a finite partially ordered set is equal to the number of its maximal elements.
- In particular, let be a set of size and consider the set of subsets of containing no more than elements. This is partially ordered under inclusion and the subsets with elements are maximal. Thus the cofinality of this poset is choose
- A subset of the natural numbers is cofinal in if and only if it is infinite, and therefore the cofinality of is Thus is a regular cardinal.
- The cofinality of the real numbers with their usual ordering is since is cofinal in The usual ordering of is not order isomorphic to the cardinality of the real numbers, which has cofinality strictly greater than This demonstrates that the cofinality depends on the order; different orders on the same set may have different cofinality.
Properties
editIf admits a totally ordered cofinal subset, then we can find a subset that is well-ordered and cofinal in Any subset of is also well-ordered. Two cofinal subsets of with minimal cardinality (that is, their cardinality is the cofinality of ) need not be order isomorphic (for example if then both and viewed as subsets of have the countable cardinality of the cofinality of but are not order isomorphic). But cofinal subsets of with minimal order type will be order isomorphic.
Cofinality of ordinals and other well-ordered sets
editThe cofinality of an ordinal is the smallest ordinal that is the order type of a cofinal subset of The cofinality of a set of ordinals or any other well-ordered set is the cofinality of the order type of that set.
Thus for a limit ordinal there exists a -indexed strictly increasing sequence with limit For example, the cofinality of is because the sequence (where ranges over the natural numbers) tends to but, more generally, any countable limit ordinal has cofinality An uncountable limit ordinal may have either cofinality as does or an uncountable cofinality.
The cofinality of 0 is 0. The cofinality of any successor ordinal is 1. The cofinality of any nonzero limit ordinal is an infinite regular cardinal.
Regular and singular ordinals
editA regular ordinal is an ordinal that is equal to its cofinality. A singular ordinal is any ordinal that is not regular.
Every regular ordinal is the initial ordinal of a cardinal. Any limit of regular ordinals is a limit of initial ordinals and thus is also initial but need not be regular. Assuming the axiom of choice, is regular for each In this case, the ordinals and are regular, whereas and are initial ordinals that are not regular.
The cofinality of any ordinal is a regular ordinal, that is, the cofinality of the cofinality of is the same as the cofinality of So the cofinality operation is idempotent.
Cofinality of cardinals
editIf is an infinite cardinal number, then is the least cardinal such that there is an unbounded function from to is also the cardinality of the smallest set of strictly smaller cardinals whose sum is more precisely
That the set above is nonempty comes from the fact that that is, the disjoint union of singleton sets. This implies immediately that The cofinality of any totally ordered set is regular, so
Using König's theorem, one can prove and for any infinite cardinal
The last inequality implies that the cofinality of the cardinality of the continuum must be uncountable. On the other hand, the ordinal number ω being the first infinite ordinal, so that the cofinality of is card(ω) = (In particular, is singular.) Therefore,
(Compare to the continuum hypothesis, which states )
Generalizing this argument, one can prove that for a limit ordinal
On the other hand, if the axiom of choice holds, then for a successor or zero ordinal
See also
edit- Club set – Set theory concept
- Initial ordinal – mathematical concept
References
edit- Jech, Thomas, 2003. Set Theory: The Third Millennium Edition, Revised and Expanded. Springer. ISBN 3-540-44085-2.
- Kunen, Kenneth, 1980. Set Theory: An Introduction to Independence Proofs. Elsevier. ISBN 0-444-86839-9.