Animal ethics is a branch of ethics which examines human-animal relationships, the moral consideration of animals and how nonhuman animals ought to be treated. The subject matter includes animal rights, animal welfare, animal law, speciesism, animal cognition, wildlife conservation, wild animal suffering,[1] the moral status of nonhuman animals, the concept of nonhuman personhood, human exceptionalism, the history of animal use, and theories of justice.[2][3] Several different theoretical approaches have been proposed to examine this field, in accordance with the different theories currently defended in moral and political philosophy.[4][5][6] There is no theory which is completely accepted due to the differing understandings of what is meant by the term ethics; however, there are theories that are more widely accepted by society such as animal rights and utilitarianism.[7][8]
History
editThe history of the regulation of animal research was a fundamental step towards the development of animal ethics, as this was when the term "animal ethics" first emerged.[9] In the beginning, the term "animal ethics" was associated solely with cruelty, only changing in the late 20th century, when it was deemed inadequate in modern society.[10] The United States Animal Welfare Act of 1966, attempted to tackle the problems of animal research; however, their effects were considered futile. Many did not support this act as it communicated that if there was human benefit resulting from the tests, the suffering of the animals was justifiable. It was not until the establishment of the animal rights movement that people started supporting and voicing their opinions in public. Animal ethics was expressed through this movement and led to big changes to the power and meaning of animal ethics.
Animal rights
editThe first animal rights laws were first introduced between 1635 and 1780. In 1635, Ireland was the first country to pass animal protection legislation, "An Act against Plowing by the Tayle, and pulling the Wooll off living Sheep".[11] In 1641, Massachusetts colony's called Body of Liberties that includes regulation against any "Tirranny or Crueltie" towards animals.[12] In 1687, Japan reintroduced a ban on eating meat and killing animals.[13] In 1789, philosopher Jeremy Bentham argued in An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation, that an animal's capacity to suffer—not their intelligence—meant that they should be granted rights: "The question is not, Can they reason? nor, Can they talk? but, Can they suffer? Why should the law refuse its protection to any sensitive being?"[14]
Between 1822 and 1892, more laws were passed to protect animals. In 1822, the British Parliament passed the Cruel Treatment of Cattle Act.[15] In 1824, the first animal rights society was founded in England by Richard Martin, Arthur Broome, Lewis Gompertz and William Wilberforce, the Society for the Prevention of Cruelty to Animals, which later became the RSPCA.[16] The same year, Gompertz published Moral Inquiries on the Situation of Man and of Brutes, one of the first books advocating for what will be more than a century later known as veganism.[17] In 1835, Britain passed the first Cruelty to Animals Act.[18] In 1866, the American Society for the Prevention of Cruelty to Animals was founded by New Yorker Henry Bergh.[19] In 1875, Frances Power Cobbe established the National Anti-Vivisection Society in Britain.[20] In 1892, English social reformer Henry Stephens Salt published Animal Rights: Considered in Relation to Social Progress.[21]
In 1970, Richard D. Ryder coined speciesism, a term for discrimination against animals based on their species-membership.[22] This term was popularized by the philosopher and ethicist Peter Singer in his 1975 book Animal Liberation. The late 1970s marked the beginnings of the animal rights movement, which portrayed the belief that animals must be recognised as sentient beings and protected from unessential harm.[23] Since the 18th century, many groups have been organised supporting different aspects of animal rights and carrying out their support in differing ways. On one hand, "The Animal Liberation Front" is an English group that took the law into their own hands, orchestrating the Penn break-in, while a group such as "People for Ethical Treatment of Animals" founded in the US, although supporting the same goals, aim for legislative gains.[24]
Animal farming
editIn 2023, it is estimated that 74% of all land livestock are factory farmed. In the United States, 99% of all livestock was estimated in 2017 to be factory farmed,[27] despite 75% of US adults thinking that the animal products they consume come from animals that are treated "humanely".[28]
Factory farming, or intensive animal farming, is characterized by densely confined animals[27] and comes with a range of issues, including:
- Confinement methods – Many animals, such as egg-laying hens, are kept in cages with limited space to move. Similarly, pregnant pigs are often kept in gestation crates, which are so small that the animals cannot turn around.[29]
- Aggressiveness – In densely confined environments without intellectual stimulation, animals tend to become aggressive, sometimes also engaging in cannibalism.[30]
- Mutilations – These procedures are often intended to reduce aggression in these environments and are typically performed without anesthetic. Examples include trimming the beaks of chickens,[31] and clipping the teeth and tails of piglets.[32][33] Piglets are also frequently castrated to avoid a bad smell that can sometimes develop in the meat. Routine tail clipping is considered a traumatic practice for pigs and is banned in Europe, but the ban is often ignored in practice.[34]
- Genetic selection – Farmed animals are typically genetically selected to increase productivity. For instance, chickens often struggle to walk to their unnatural weight, which can also lead to heart and lung problems.[35]
- Diseases – The lack of genetic diversity and the density of animals in confinement can lead to the spread of diseases, some of which can also be transmitted to humans.[36]
- Artificial insemination – Animals are frequently impregnated through artificial insemination, a process carried out by humans.[37]
- Early separations from mothers[37]
- Stress[37]
Despite their vast numbers, factory farmed animals are relatively ignored. Species that appear more different from humans, such as fish or insects, are often particularly overlooked.[38][39]
Intensive animal farming is sometimes described as one of the worst moral catastrophes in history.[26][40] According to Jacy Reese Anthis, even farms considered high-welfare typically have serious welfare issues, notably due to genetic selection. He argues that truly ethical animal farms would be prohibitively expensive for consumers.[28] Movements such as "conscientious omnivores" oppose factory farming but not all animal farming.[41] Peter Singer suggests that even as a vegan, there are a few exceptions like oysters that are ethically acceptable to eat because they cannot suffer and their farming is environmentally sustainable.[41]
One proposed solution to reduce farmed animal suffering is to develop plant-based and cultured alternatives to animal products.[42][43]
Insects
editThere is uncertainty on whether insects are sentient and can feel pain.[44] Insects often continue normal feeding and mating behaviours after catastrophic injuries. But they display aversive experiences to other stimuli like heat.[45] Studies on bees notably showed multiple markers of sentience, such as the ability to strategically avoid threats or harmful situations unless the reward is significant.[46]
The rapidly growing industry of insect farming is often presented as a solution to the environmental degradation caused by traditional animal farming. But a significant part of the crops fed to insects is edible for human, and farmed insects are often fed to livestock rather than directly to humans, which increases inefficiency.[47] In 2023, more than one trillion insects were farmed annually, with little to no formal welfare standards in place, leaving companies to determine their own practices.[44]
Animal testing
editAnimal testing for biomedical research dates to the writings of the ancient Greeks.[48] It is understood that physician-scientists such as Aristotle, and Erasistratus carried out experiments on living animals.[48] After them, there was also Galen, who was Greek but resided in Rome, carrying out experiments on living animals to improve on the knowledge of anatomy, physiology, pathology, and pharmacology.[48] Animal testing since has evolved considerably and is still being carried out in the modern-day, with millions of experimental animals being used around the world.[49] However, during recent years it has come under severe criticism by the public and animal activist groups. Those against, argue that the benefits that animal testing provides for humanity are not justifiable for the suffering of those animals. Those for, argue that animal testing is fundamental for the advancement of biomedical knowledge.
Drug testing on animals blew up in the 20th century. In 1937, a US pharmaceutical company created an infamous drug called "Elixir Sulfanilamide". This drug had a chemical called DEG in it which is toxic to humans, but at the time was not known to be harmful to humans. Without precautions, the drug was released to the public and was responsible for a mass poisoning. The DEG ended up killing over a hundred people, causing uproar among civilisation.[48] Thus, in 1938 the U.S. Food and Drug Administration (FDA) established the Federal Food, Drug and Cosmetic Act.[50] This ensured the testing of drugs on animals before marketing of the product, to confirm that it would have no harmful implications on humans.
However, since the regulations have been put in place, animal testing deaths have increased. More than one million animals are killed from testing every year in the US.[51] In addition, the deaths of these animals are considered sickening; from inhaling toxic gas, having skin burned off, getting holes drilled into their skulls.
The Three Rs
editThe Three Rs were first introduced in a 1959 book called "The Principles of Humane Experimental technique" by zoologist W. M. S. Russell, and microbiologist R. L. Burch.[52] The Three Rs stand for Replacement, Reduction, and Refinement and are the guiding principles for the ethical treatment of animals used for testing and experimentation:[53]
- Replacement: Avoiding using an animal for testing by switching out the animal for something non-living, such as a computer model, or an animal which is less susceptible to pain in relation to the experiment.
- Reduction: Devising a plan to use the fewest animals possible; a combination of using fewer animals to gain sufficient data, and maximising the amount of data from each animal to use fewer animals.
- Refinement: A decrease in any unnecessary pain inflicted on the animal; adapting experimental procedures to minimise suffering.[54]
The Three Rs principles are now widely accepted by many countries and are used in any practises that involve the experimentation of animals.
Ethical guidelines for animal research
editThere is a wide range of ethical assessments regarding animals used in research. There are general opinions that animals do have a moral status and how they are treated should be subjected to ethical consideration; some of the positions include:
- Animals have intrinsic values that must be respected.
- Animals can feel pain and their interests must be taken into consideration.
- Our treatment of all animals/lab animals reflects on our attitudes and influences us on our moral beings.[55]
The Norwegian National Committee for Research Ethics in Science and Technology (NENT) have a set of ethical guidelines for the use of animals in research:
- Respect Animal Dignity: Researchers must have respect towards the animals' worth, regardless of their value and the animals' interests as living, sentient creatures. Researchers have to have respect when choosing their topics/methods, and when expanding their research. Researchers also have to supply care that is adapted to needs to each laboratory animal.[55]
- Responsibility for considering options (Replace): When there are alternatives available, researchers are responsible for studying those alternatives for animal experimentation. When there are no good alternatives available, researchers have to consider if the research can be postponed until a good alternative are developed. While being able to justify the experiments on animals, researchers then have to be accountable for the absence of alternative options and the urge to obtain the knowledge immediately.[55]
- The principle of proportionality: responsibility for considering and balancing suffering and benefit: Researchers have to consider both the risks of pain and suffering that laboratory animals will face and assess them in the value of the relationship to the research of animals, people, and the environment. Researchers have a responsibility on whether or not the research will have improvements for the animals, people or the environment. All of the possible benefits of the study has to be considered, substantiated and specified in both the short and long run. This responsibility also entails the obligation to consider both the scientific quality of the experiment and whether or not the experiment will have relevant scientific benefits. Suffering can only be caused by animals if there is a counterbalance of substantial and probable benefits for animals, people or the environment. Since there are many methods of analyzing the harm and the benefits, research institutions have to provide training on suitable models and researchers have the responsibility to use the methods of analysis when planning any experiments on animals (see guideline 5).[55]
- Responsibility for considering reducing the number of animals (Reduce): Researchers have the responsibility to consider whether or not it's acceptable to reduce the number of animals that an experiment's plan on using and include the number necessary to both the scientific quality of the experiments and the relevance to the results only. Before the experiment, researchers have to conduct reading studies and consider alternative designs and perform the calculations that are needed before beginning an experiment.[55]
- Responsibility for minimizing the risk of suffering and improving animal welfare (Refine): Researchers have the responsibility to assess the expected effect on laboratory animals. Researchers have to lessen the risk of suffering and provide excellent animal welfare. Suffering includes pain, hunger, malnutrition, thirst, abnormal cold/heat. fear, stress, illness, injury, and restrictions to where the animal cannot be able to behave naturally and normally. To find out what is a considerable amount of suffering, a researcher's assessment should be based on which animal suffers the most. Considering the animals is the deciding factor if there are any doubts about regarding the suffering the animals will face. Researchers have to consider the direct suffering that the animal might endure during an experiment, but there are risks before and after the suffering, including breeding, transportation, trapping, euthanizing, labeling, anesthetizing, and stabling. This means that all the researchers have to take into account the needs of periods for adaptation before and after an experiment.[55]
- Responsibility for maintaining biological diversity: Researchers are also responsible for ensuring that the use of laboratory animals do not disrupt or endanger biological diversity. This means that researchers have to consider the consequences to the stock and their ecosystem as a whole. The use of endangered species has to be reduced to a minimum. When there is credible and uncertain knowledge that the inclusion of animals in research and the use of certain methods may have ethically unacceptable consequences for the stock and the ecosystem as a whole, researchers must observe the precautionary principle.
- Responsibility when intervening in a habitat: Researchers have a responsibility for reducing the disruption and any impact of the natural behaviors of the animals, including those who are not direct test subjects in research, as well as the population and their surroundings. Most research and technology-related projects, like the ones regarding environmental technology and surveillance, might impact the animals and their living arrangements. In those cases, researchers have to seek to observe the principle of proportionality and to decrease possible negative impact(see guideline 3).[55]
- Responsibility for openness and sharing of data and material: Researchers have the responsibility for ensuring the transparency of the research findings and facilitating sharing the data and materials from all animal experiments. Transparency and sharing are important in order to not repeat the same experiments on animals. Transparency is also important in order to release the data to the public and a part of researchers' responsibility for dissimulation. Negative results of the experiments on animals have should be public knowledge. Releasing negative results to other researchers could give them more on the information about which experiments that are not worth pursuing, shine a light on unfortunate research designs, and can help reduce the number of animals used in research.
- Requirement of expertise on animals: Researchers and other parties who work and handle live animals are required to have adequate and updated documentation expertise on all animals. This includes knowledge about the biology of the animal species in question, and willingly be able to take care of the animals properly.
- Requirement of due care: There are many laws, rules, international convention, and agreements regarding the laboratory animals that both the researchers and the research managers have to comply with. Anyone who wants to use animals in experiments should familiarize themselves with the current rules.[55]
Ethical theories
editThis section is written like a personal reflection, personal essay, or argumentative essay that states a Wikipedia editor's personal feelings or presents an original argument about a topic. (July 2020) |
Ethical thinking has influenced the way society perceives animal ethics in at least three ways. Firstly, the original rise of animal ethics and how animals should be treated. Secondly, the evolution of animal ethics as people started to realise that this ideology was not as simple as was first proposed. The third way, is through the challenges humans face contemplating these ethics; consistency of morals, and the justification of some cases.[56]
Consequentialism
editConsequentialism is a collection of ethical theories which judge the rightness or wrongness of an action on its consequences; if the actions brings more benefit than harm, it is good, if it brings more harm than benefit, it is bad.[57] The most well-known type of consequentialism theory is utilitarianism.[58][59]
The publication of Peter Singer's book Animal Liberation, in 1975, gathered sizeable traction and provided him with a platform to speak his mind on the issues of animal rights.[56] Due to the attention Singer received, his views were the most accessible, and therefore best known by the public. He supported the theory of utilitarianism, which is still a controversial but highly regarded foundation for animal research. The theory of utilitarianism states that "an action is right if and only if it produces a better balance of benefits and harms than available alternative actions", thus, this theory determines whether or not something is right by weighing the pleasure against the suffering of the result.[56] It is not concerned with the process, only the weight of the consequence against the process, and while the consequentialism theory suggests if an action is bad or good, utilitarianism only focuses on the benefit of the outcome. While this may be able to be applied to some animal research and raising for food, several objections have been raised against utilitarianism. Singer made his decision to support utilitarianism on the basis of sentience, selecting that aspect as the differential factor between human and animals; the ability of self-consciousness, autonomy and to act morally.[56] This ended up being called "The argument from marginal cases".[56] However, critics allege that not all morally relevant beings fall under this category, for instance, some people with in a persistent vegetative state who have no awareness of themselves or their surroundings.[60] Based on Singer's arguments, it would be as (or more) justified to carry out experiments in medical research on these non-sentient humans than on other (sentient) animals. Another limitation of applying utilitarianism to animal ethics is that it is difficult to accurately measure and compare the suffering of the harmed animals to the gains of the beneficiaries, for instance, in medical experiments.
Jeff Sebo argues that utilitarianism has three main implications for animal ethics: "First, utilitarianism plausibly implies that all vertebrates and at least some invertebrates morally matter, and that large animals like elephants matter more on average and that small animals like ants might matter more in total. Second, utilitarianism plausibly implies that we morally ought to attempt to both promote animal welfare and respect animal rights in many real-life cases. Third, utilitarianism plausibly implies that we should prioritize farmed and wild animal welfare and pursue a variety of interventions at once to make progress on these issues".[8]
Deontology
editDeontology is a theory that evaluates moral actions based only on doing one's duty, not on the consequences of the actions.[61] This means that if it is your duty to carry out a task, it is morally right regardless of the consequences, and if you fail to do your duty, you are morally wrong. There are many types of deontological theories, however, the one most commonly recognised is often associated with Immanuel Kant.[62] This ethical theory can be implemented from conflicting sides, for example, a researcher may think it is their duty to make an animal suffer to find a cure for a disease that is affecting millions of humans, which according to deontology is morally correct. On the other hand, an animal activist might think that saving these animals being tested on is their duty, creating a contradiction in this idea. Furthermore, another conflicting nature of this theory is when you must choose between two imposing moral duties, such as deciding if you should lie about where an escaped chicken went, or if you should tell the truth and send the chicken to its death. Lying is an immoral duty to carry out, however, so is sending a chicken to its death.
A highlighted flaw in Kant's theory is that it was not applicable to non-human animals, only specifically to humans.[61] This theory opposes utilitarianism in the sense that instead of concerning itself with the consequence, it focuses on the duty. However, both are fundamental theories that contribute to animal ethics.
Virtue ethics
editVirtue ethics does not pinpoint on either the consequences or duty of the action, but from the act of behaving like a virtuous person.[63] Thus, asking if such actions would stem from a virtuous person or someone with a vicious nature. If it would stem from someone virtuous, it is said that it is morally right, and if from a vicious person, immoral behaviour. A virtuous person is said to hold qualities such as respect, tolerance, justice and equality. One advantage that this theory has over the others, is that it takes into account human emotions, affecting the moral decision, which was absent in the previous two. However, a flaw is that people's opinions of a virtuous person are very subjective, and thus, can drastically affect the person's moral compass. With this underlying issue, this ethical theory cannot be applied to all cases.
Relationship with environmental ethics
editDiffering conceptions of the treatment of and duties towards animals, particularly those living in the wild, within animal ethics and environmental ethics have been a source of conflict between the two ethical positions; some philosophers have made a case that the two positions are incompatible,[64] while others have argued that such disagreements can be overcome.[65]
See also
editReferences
edit- ^ Moen, Ole Martin (2016-05-09). "The ethics of wild animal suffering". Etikk I Praksis – Nordic Journal of Applied Ethics. 10 (1): 91–104. doi:10.5324/eip.v10i1.1972. ISSN 1890-4009.
- ^ Beauchamp, Tom L. "Introduction", in Tom L. Beauchamp and R.G. Frey. The Oxford Handbook of Animal Ethics. Oxford University Press, 2011.
- ^ Schaffner, Joan E. An Introduction to Animals and the Law. Palgrave MacMillan, 2011, p. xvii
- ^ Wilson, Scott. 2001. "Animals and ethics." in Fieser, James & Dowden, Bradley (eds.) Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- ^ Armstrong, Susan J. & Botzler, Richard G. (eds.). 2003. The Animal Ethics Reader. New York: Routledge.
- ^ "Ethical theories and nonhuman animals". Animal Ethics. Retrieved 2020-04-27.
- ^ Ideland, M. (2009-04-01). "Different views on ethics: how animal ethics is situated in a committee culture". Journal of Medical Ethics. 35 (4): 258–261. doi:10.1136/jme.2008.026989. hdl:2043/8746. ISSN 0306-6800. PMID 19332584. S2CID 27790049.
- ^ a b Sebo, Jeff (2021). "Utilitarianism and Nonhuman Animals". Utilitarianism.net. Retrieved 2021-11-06.
- ^ Rollin, Bernard E. "The regulation of animal research and the emergence of animal ethics: a conceptual history." Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 27.4 (2006): 285-304.
- ^ Rollin, Bernard E. (2006). "The regulation of animal research and the emergence of animal ethics: a conceptual history" (PDF). Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics. 27 (4): 285–304. doi:10.1007/s11017-006-9007-8. ISSN 1386-7415. PMID 16937023. S2CID 18620094. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2020-10-08. Retrieved 2020-09-14.
- ^ Gannett, Jennifer (2011). "Confronting Animal Abuse: Law, Criminology, and Human-Animal Relationships" (PDF). Journal for Critical Animal Studies. 9.
- ^ "1641: Massachusetts Body of Liberties". Online Library of Liberty. Retrieved 2019-10-14.
- ^ White, Chris (2014-07-08). "Vegetarian Japan: A short history". JapanTravel. Retrieved 2019-10-14.
- ^ Bentham, Jeremy (1789). Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation.
- ^ Uvarov, Dame Olga (January 1985). "Research with animals: requirement, responsibility, welfare". Laboratory Animals. 19 (1): 51–75. doi:10.1258/002367785780890640. ISSN 0023-6772. PMID 3883054. S2CID 35799876.
- ^ "The History of the RSPCA". Animal Legal & Historical Center. 1972. Retrieved 2020-07-26.
- ^ Gompertz, Lewis (1992) [1824]. Singer, Peter (ed.). Moral Inquiries on the Situation of Man and of Brutes. Fontwell, Sussex: Centaur Press. ISBN 978-0-900001-37-6. OCLC 27752919.
- ^ Carr, Daniel James (2017-10-31). "The Historical Development of Animal Welfare Law in Nineteenth Century Scotland". Rochester, New York. SSRN 3062845.
{{cite journal}}
: Cite journal requires|journal=
(help) - ^ "History of the ASPCA". ASPCA. Retrieved 2019-10-14.
- ^ "The history of the NAVS". National Anti-Vivisection Society. 2012-07-24. Retrieved 2020-07-26.
- ^ "Animals' Rights, Considered in Relation to Social Progress". Henry S. Salt Society. Retrieved 2020-07-26.
- ^ Ryder, Richard D. (Spring 2010) [1970]. "Speciesism Again: The Original Leaflet" (PDF). Critical Society. 2. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2012-11-14.
- ^ Francione, Gary L. (1995–1996). "Animal Rights and Animal Welfare". Rutgers Law Review. 48: 397.
- ^ Robbins, William (1984-06-15). "Animal Rights: A Growing Movement in U.s." The New York Times. ISSN 0362-4331. Retrieved 2020-07-26.
- ^ "More than 80 billion land animals are slaughtered for meat every year". Our World in Data. Retrieved 2024-09-12.
- ^ a b Bolotnikova, Marina (2024-08-07). "How Factory Farming Ends". Vox. Retrieved 2024-09-12.
- ^ a b Ritchie, Hannah; Roser, Max (2024-02-24). "How many animals are factory-farmed?". Our World in Data.
- ^ a b Reese, Jacy (2018-11-16). "There's no such thing as humane meat or eggs. Stop kidding yourself". The Guardian. ISSN 0261-3077. Retrieved 2024-09-12.
- ^ Torrella, Kenny (2021-08-10). "The fight over cage-free eggs and bacon in California, explained". Vox. Retrieved 2024-09-12.
- ^ Torrella, Kenny (2023-11-22). "How America broke the turkey". Vox. Retrieved 2024-09-12.
- ^ Williams, Zoe (2020-03-09). "Beak-trimming and brutality: is it time to stop buying brown eggs?". The Guardian. ISSN 0261-3077. Retrieved 2024-09-12.
- ^ Matthews, Dylan (2019-11-22). "An easy way to make piglet lives better". Vox. Retrieved 2024-09-12.
- ^ "Allegations of animal cruelty and a bestiality charge at Victorian piggery". ABC News. 2024-03-11. Retrieved 2024-09-12.
- ^ Ferrara, Cecilia; Nelson, Catherine (2019-01-19). "The curse of tail-docking: the painful truth about Italy's pigs". The Guardian. ISSN 0261-3077. Retrieved 2024-09-12.
- ^ Torrella, Kenny (2022-03-25). "Gene editing could upend the future of factory farming — for better or worse". Vox. Retrieved 2024-09-12.
- ^ Vidal, John (2021-10-18). "Factory farms of disease: how industrial chicken production is breeding the next pandemic". The Guardian. ISSN 0261-3077. Retrieved 2024-09-12.
- ^ a b c Jacobs, Andrew (December 29, 2020). "Is Dairy Farming Cruel to Cows?". The New York Times.
- ^ Woodruff, Michael (July 3, 2020). "Fish are nothing like us, except that they are sentient beings". Aeon. Retrieved 2024-09-19.
- ^ Reynolds, Matt (March 16, 2023). "Insect Farming Is Booming. But Is It Cruel?". Wired. ISSN 1059-1028. Retrieved 2024-06-06.
- ^ Harari, Yuval Noah (2015-09-25). "Industrial farming is one of the worst crimes in history". The Guardian. ISSN 0261-3077. Retrieved 2024-09-12.
- ^ a b Corbyn, Zoë (2023-05-21). "Philosopher Peter Singer: 'There's no reason to say humans have more worth or moral status than animals'". The Observer. ISSN 0029-7712. Retrieved 2024-09-12.
- ^ Illing, Sean (2016-10-11). "Ethical arguments won't end factory farming. Technology might". Vox. Retrieved 2024-09-12.
- ^ Piper, Kelsey (2018-11-15). "We could end factory farming this century". Vox. Retrieved 2024-09-12.
- ^ a b Reynolds, Matt. "Insect Farming Is Booming. But Is It Cruel?". Wired. ISSN 1059-1028. Retrieved 2024-06-06.
- ^ Birch, Jonathan (2024-07-19). "13.6 Summary of Chapter 13". The Edge of Sentience: Risk and Precaution in Humans, Other Animals, and AI. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-196672-9.
- ^ Chittka, Lars (2023-07-01). "Do Insects Feel Joy and Pain?". Scientific American. Retrieved 2024-06-08.
- ^ Lymbery, Philip (2023-07-27). "Insect Farming Isn't Going to Save the Planet". TIME. Retrieved 2024-09-12.
- ^ a b c d Hajar, Rachel (2011). "Animal Testing and Medicine". Heart Views. 12 (1): 42. doi:10.4103/1995-705X.81548. ISSN 1995-705X. PMC 3123518. PMID 21731811.
- ^ Doke, Sonali K.; Dhawale, Shashikant C. (2015-07-01). "Alternatives to animal testing: A review". Saudi Pharmaceutical Journal. 23 (3): 223–229. doi:10.1016/j.jsps.2013.11.002. ISSN 1319-0164. PMC 4475840. PMID 26106269.
- ^ Schechtman, Leonard M. (2002). "The safety assessment process—setting the scene: an FDA perspective". ILAR Journal. 43 Suppl: S5–10. doi:10.1093/ilar.43.suppl_1.s5. ISSN 1084-2020. PMID 12388844.
- ^ "Experiments on Animals: Overview". PETA. 2004-11-11. Retrieved 2020-07-26.
- ^ Zurlo, J; Rudacille, D; Goldberg, A M (August 1996). "The three Rs: the way forward". Environmental Health Perspectives. 104 (8): 878–880. doi:10.1289/ehp.96104878. ISSN 0091-6765. PMC 1469425. PMID 8875163.
- ^ "Laboratory Animal Ethics: The Three Rs". Bitesize Bio. 2017-02-21. Retrieved 2019-04-24.
- ^ Badyal, Dinesh K.; Desai, Chetna (2014). "Animal use in pharmacology education and research: The changing scenario". Indian Journal of Pharmacology. 46 (3): 257–65. doi:10.4103/0253-7613.132153. PMC 4071700. PMID 24987170.
- ^ a b c d e f g h "Ethical Guidelines for the Use of Animals in Research: Text: The Norwegian National Committees for Research Ethics Photo: Maiken Aa Solbakken". Etikkom. September 24, 2018. Retrieved 2019-04-22.
- ^ a b c d e Russow, Lilly-Marlene (1999-01-01). "Bioethics, Animal Research, and Ethical Theory". ILAR Journal. 40 (1): 15–21. doi:10.1093/ilar.40.1.15. ISSN 1084-2020. PMID 11533512.
- ^ Sinnott-Armstrong, Walter (2019), "Consequentialism", in Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2019 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 2020-07-26
- ^ "Ethics Explainer: What is Consequentialism?". The Ethics Center. 2016-02-15. Retrieved 2020-07-26.
- ^ MacAskill, William; Chappell, Richard (2020). "Elements and Types of Utilitarianism". Utilitarianism.net. Retrieved 2021-11-06.
- ^ Multi-Society Task Force on PVS (1994-06-02). "Medical Aspects of the Persistent Vegetative State". New England Journal of Medicine. 330 (22): 1572–1579. doi:10.1056/NEJM199406023302206. ISSN 0028-4793. PMID 8177248.
- ^ a b Misselbrook, David (April 2013). "Duty, Kant, and Deontology". The British Journal of General Practice. 63 (609): 211. doi:10.3399/bjgp13X665422. ISSN 0960-1643. PMC 3609464. PMID 23540473.
- ^ Secker, B. (February 1999). "The appearance of Kant's deontology in contemporary Kantianism: concepts of patient autonomy in bioethics". The Journal of Medicine and Philosophy. 24 (1): 43–66. doi:10.1076/jmep.24.1.43.2544. ISSN 0360-5310. PMID 10223442.
- ^ Hursthouse, Rosalind (2011-10-26). Beauchamp, Tom L; Frey, R. G (eds.). "Virtue Ethics and the Treatment of Animals". The Oxford Handbook of Animal Ethics. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780195371963.001.0001. ISBN 9780195371963. Retrieved 2020-07-26.
- ^ Faria, Catia; Paez, Eze (July 2019). "It's Splitsville: Why Animal Ethics and Environmental Ethics Are Incompatible". American Behavioral Scientist. 63 (8): 1047–1060. doi:10.1177/0002764219830467. ISSN 0002-7642. S2CID 150854523.
- ^ Callicott, J. Baird (1988-07-01). "Animal Liberation and Environmental Ethics: Back Together Again". Between the Species. 4 (3). doi:10.15368/bts.1988v4n3.1.
Further reading
edit- Fischer, Bob. Animal Ethics: A Contemporary Introduction. Routledge, 2021.
- Korsgaard, Christine M. Fellow Creatures: Our Obligations to the Other Animals. Oxford University Press, 2018
- Frasch, Pamela D. et al. Animal Law in a Nutshell. West, 2010.
- Gruen, Lori. Ethics and Animals: An Introduction. Cambridge University Press, 2011.
- Rowlands, Mark. Animals Like Us. Verso, 2002.
- Sunstein, Cass R. and Nussbaum, Martha (eds). Animal Rights: Current Debates and New Directions. Oxford University Press, 2005.
- Taylor, Angus. Animals and Ethics: An Overview of the Philosophical Debate, 3rd ed. Broadview Press, 2009.
- Wagman, Bruce A.; Waisman, Sonia S.; Frasch, Pamela D. Animal Law: Cases and Materials. Carolina Academic Press, 2009.
- Waldau, Paul. Animal Rights: What Everyone Needs to Know. Oxford University Press, 2011.
External links
edit- Scott Wilson. "Animals and Ethics". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- "The Moral Status of Animals" entry by Lori Gruen in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
- Jeff Sebo (2021), Utilitarianism and Nonhuman Animals, in William MacAskill & Richard Chappell, An Introduction to Utilitarianism