Analytical Thomism is a philosophical movement which promotes the interchange of ideas between the thought of Thomas Aquinas (including the philosophy carried on in relation to his thinking, called 'Thomism'), and modern analytic philosophy.
Scottish philosopher John Haldane first coined the term in the early 1990s and has since been one of the movement's leading proponents. According to Haldane, "analytical Thomism involves the bringing into mutual relationship of the styles and preoccupations of recent English-speaking philosophy and the ideas and concerns shared by St Thomas and his followers".[1]
History 19th century—World War
editThe modern revival of Aquinas's thought can be traced to the work of mid-19th Century thomists, such as Tommaso Maria Zigliara, Josef Kleutgen, Gaetano Sanseverino, and Giovanni Maria Cornoldi. This movement received an enormous impetus by Pope Leo XIII's encyclical Aeterni Patris of 1879. In the first half of the twentieth century, Edouard Hugon, Réginald Garrigou-Lagrange, Étienne Gilson, and Jacques Maritain, among others, carried on Leo's call for a Thomist revival.[2] Gilson and Maritain in particular taught and lectured throughout Europe and North America, influencing a generation of English-speaking Catholic philosophers. Some of the latter then began to harmonize Thomism with broader contemporary philosophical trends.
Similarly, the Kraków Circle in Poland used mathematical logic in presenting Thomism, which the Circle judged to have "a structured body of propositions connected in meaning and subject matter, and linked by logical relations of compatibility and incompatibility, entailment, etc."[3] The Circle has been said to be "the most significant expression of Catholic thought between the two World Wars".[4]
Postwar philosophical reception of Aquinas
editBy the middle of the 20th century Aquinas's thought came into dialogue with the analytical tradition through the work of G. E. M. Anscombe, Peter Geach, and Anthony Kenny. Anscombe was Ludwig Wittgenstein's student, and his successor at the University of Cambridge; she was married to Geach, himself an accomplished logician and philosopher of religion. Geach had converted to Roman Catholicism while studying at Oxford, Anscombe had converted before she came up, and both were instructed in the Faith in Oxford by the Dominican Richard Kehoe, who received them both into the Church before they met one another. Kenny, an erstwhile priest and former Catholic, became a prominent philosopher at the University of Oxford and an editor and executor of Wittgenstein's literary estate, and is still portrayed by some as a promoter of Aquinas (Paterson & Pugh, xiii-xxiii), though his denial of some basic Thomist doctrines (e.g. divine timelessness) casts doubt on this.
Anscombe, and other Aristotelians such as Alasdair MacIntyre, Philippa Foot, Mortimer Adler, and John Finnis, can largely be credited with the revival of "virtue ethics" in analytic moral theory and "natural law theory" in jurisprudence. Both movements draw significantly upon Aquinas.
Notable analytical Thomists
editPhilosophers and theologians working in the intersection of Thomism and analytic philosophy include:
- Michael Staron (Saint Anselm's Abbey School)
- Mortimer Adler (1902-2001)
- David Braine
- John C. Cahalan (independent scholar)
- Brian Davies (Fordham)
- Gabriele De Anna (Udine) (Bamberg)
- Edward Feser
- John Finnis (Oxford)
- Peter Geach (Deceased)
- John Haldane (St Andrews) (Baylor University)
- Simon Hewitt (Leeds)
- Jonathan Jacobs (Colgate)
- Anthony Kenny (Oxford)
- Fergus Kerr (Oxford)
- Gyula Klima (Fordham)
- Norman Kretzmann
- John Lamont
- Elizabeth Anscombe (Deceased)
- Anthony J. Lisska (Denison)
- Alasdair MacIntyre (Notre Dame)
- Bruce D. Marshall (Southern Methodist Univ)
- William Marshner (Christendom)
- Christopher Martin (St Thomas, Houston)
- Cyrille Michon (Nantes, France)
- Mark Murphy (Georgetown)
- Herbert McCabe (Deceased)
- John P. O'Callaghan (Notre Dame)
- Robert Pasnau (CU Boulder)
- Craig Paterson (Independent Scholar)
- Roger Pouivet (Nancy, France)
- Alexander Pruss (Baylor University)
- Matthew S. Pugh (Providence College)
- Eleonore Stump (Saint Louis)
- Thomas Sullivan and Sandra Menssen (University of St. Thomas, MN)
- Stephen Theron, Denys Turner (Yale), Michael Thompson (Pittsburgh)
- Giovanni Ventimiglia (Lugano, Switzerland)
- James Madden (Benedictine College)
- Jeffrey Brower (Purdue University)
- Andrew Jaeger (Benedictine College)
- Robert Alspaugh (St. Anselm's Abbey School)
- Christopher Bobier (Central Michigan University)
- T. Adam Van Wart (Ave Maria University)
- David Burrell
- Michał Głowala (University of Wroclaw)
See also
edit- Józef Maria Bocheński (Cracow Circle Thomism)
- Meta-ethics
- Philosophy of religion
- Neo-scholasticism
- Richard Swinburne – English philosopher and Christian apologist
References
editCitations
edit- ^ Haldane 2004, p. xii.
- ^ Paterson & Pugh 2006, pp. xiii–xxiii.
- ^ Simons 2003, pp. 281–297.
- ^ Murawski 2014, pp. 359–376.
Sources
edit- Haldane, John (2004). Faithful Reason: essays Catholic and Philosophical. London and New York: Routledge.
- Murawski, Roman (2014). "Cracow Circle and Its Philosophy of Logic and Mathematics". Axiomathes. 25 (3): 359–376. doi:10.1007/s10516-014-9256-5. ISSN 1122-1151.
- Paterson, Craig; Pugh, Matthew S., eds. (2006). "Introduction" (PDF). Analytical Thomism: Traditions in Dialogue. Aldershot and Burlington, Vt.: Ashgate. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2011-05-26.
- Simons, Peter (2003). "Bocheński and Balance: System and History in Analytic Philosophy". Studies in East European Thought. 55 (4): 281–297. doi:10.1023/A:1025344204927. hdl:2262/61823. ISSN 0925-9392. S2CID 142830603., reprinted in Edgar Morscher, Otto Neumaier, and Peter Simons (2011), Ein Philosoph mit "Bodenhaftung": Zu Leben und Werk von Joseph M. Bocheński, Sankt Augustin: Academia, pp. 61-79.
Further reading
edit- Alfred Freddoso, Two Roles for Catholic Philosophers
- Brian J Shanley, OP, The Thomist Tradition (Dordrecht/Boston/London: Kluwer, 2002).
- Entries by Stephen Theron in Haldane (ed.) (1997) and Paterson & Pugh (eds.) (2006).
- Entries by Shanley and John Knasas in Paterson & Pugh (eds.) (2006).
- "Tomismo analitico" [Analytical Thomism] (in Spanish).
- John C. Cahalan, Causal Realism: An Essay on Philosophical Method and the Foundations of Knowledge (Routledge, 1985)
- Copleston, F.C. (1955). Aquinas. Penguin.
- John Finnis, Aquinas: Moral, Political, and Legal Theory (Oxford, 1998).
- John Haldane (ed.), "Analytical Thomism" volume of Monist 80 (4) October, 1997.
- Haldane, John (1999). "Thomism and the Future of Catholic Philosophy". New Blackfriars. 80 (938): 158–169. doi:10.1111/j.1741-2005.1999.tb01656.x. ISSN 0028-4289.
- Kerr, Fergus (2004). "Aquinas and Analytic Philosophy: Natural Allies?". Modern Theology. 20 (1): 123–139. doi:10.1111/j.1468-0025.2004.00245.x. ISSN 0266-7177.
- Anthony J Lisska,Aquinas's Theory of Natural Law: An Analytic Reconstruction (Oxford: New York, 1996).
- Pérez de Laborda, Miguel, "El tomismo analítico", Philosophica: Enciclopedia filosófica on line 2007
- Bruce D. Marshall, Trinity and Truth (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999).
- Roger Pouivet, Après Wittgenstein, saint Thomas (PUF, 1997).
- T. Adam Van Wart, Neither Nature nor Grace: Aquinas, Barth, and Garrigou-Lagrange on the Epistemic Use of God's Effects (Washington, D.C.: Catholic University of America Press, 2020).
- Michał Głowała, Możności i ich akty. Studium z tomizmu analitycznego (Oficyna Wydawnicza Atut - Wrocławskie Wydawnictwo Oświatowe, 2016).
- Ventimiglia, Giovanni (2012). To be o esse? La questione dell'essere nel tomismo analitico [To be or them? The question of being in analytic Thomism]. Rome: Carocci.