Non-well-founded set theories are variants of axiomatic set theory that allow sets to be elements of themselves and otherwise violate the rule of well-foundedness. In non-well-founded set theories, the foundation axiom of ZFC is replaced by axioms implying its negation.
The study of non-well-founded sets was initiated by Dmitry Mirimanoff in a series of papers between 1917 and 1920, in which he formulated the distinction between well-founded and non-well-founded sets; he did not regard well-foundedness as an axiom. Although a number of axiomatic systems of non-well-founded sets were proposed afterwards, they did not find much in the way of applications until the book Non-Well-Founded Sets by Peter Aczel introduces hyperset theory in 1988.[1][2][3]
The theory of non-well-founded sets has been applied in the logical modelling of non-terminating computational processes in computer science (process algebra and final semantics), linguistics and natural language semantics (situation theory), philosophy (work on the Liar Paradox), and in a different setting, non-standard analysis.[4]
Details
editIn 1917, Dmitry Mirimanoff introduced[5][6][7][8] the concept of well-foundedness of a set:
- A set, x0, is well-founded if it has no infinite descending membership sequence
In ZFC, there is no infinite descending ∈-sequence by the axiom of regularity. In fact, the axiom of regularity is often called the foundation axiom since it can be proved within ZFC− (that is, ZFC without the axiom of regularity) that well-foundedness implies regularity. In variants of ZFC without the axiom of regularity, the possibility of non-well-founded sets with set-like ∈-chains arises. For example, a set A such that A ∈ A is non-well-founded.
Although Mirimanoff also introduced a notion of isomorphism between possibly non-well-founded sets, he considered neither an axiom of foundation nor of anti-foundation.[7] In 1926, Paul Finsler introduced the first axiom that allowed non-well-founded sets. After Zermelo adopted Foundation into his own system in 1930 (from previous work of von Neumann 1925–1929) interest in non-well-founded sets waned for decades.[9] An early non-well-founded set theory was Willard Van Orman Quine’s New Foundations, although it is not merely ZF with a replacement for Foundation.
Several proofs of the independence of Foundation from the rest of ZF were published in 1950s particularly by Paul Bernays (1954), following an announcement of the result in an earlier paper of his from 1941, and by Ernst Specker who gave a different proof in his Habilitationsschrift of 1951, proof which was published in 1957. Then in 1957 Rieger's theorem was published, which gave a general method for such proof to be carried out, rekindling some interest in non-well-founded axiomatic systems.[10] The next axiom proposal came in a 1960 congress talk of Dana Scott (never published as a paper), proposing an alternative axiom now called SAFA.[11] Another axiom proposed in the late 1960s was Maurice Boffa's axiom of superuniversality, described by Aczel as the highpoint of research of its decade.[12] Boffa's idea was to make foundation fail as badly as it can (or rather, as extensionality permits): Boffa's axiom implies that every extensional set-like relation is isomorphic to the elementhood predicate on a transitive class.
A more recent approach to non-well-founded set theory, pioneered by M. Forti and F. Honsell in the 1980s, borrows from computer science the concept of a bisimulation. Bisimilar sets are considered indistinguishable and thus equal, which leads to a strengthening of the axiom of extensionality. In this context, axioms contradicting the axiom of regularity are known as anti-foundation axioms, and a set that is not necessarily well-founded is called a hyperset.
Four mutually independent anti-foundation axioms are well-known, sometimes abbreviated by the first letter in the following list:
- AFA ("Anti-Foundation Axiom") – due to M. Forti and F. Honsell (this is also known as Aczel's anti-foundation axiom);
- SAFA ("Scott’s AFA") – due to Dana Scott,
- FAFA ("Finsler’s AFA") – due to Paul Finsler,
- BAFA ("Boffa’s AFA") – due to Maurice Boffa.
They essentially correspond to four different notions of equality for non-well-founded sets. The first of these, AFA, is based on accessible pointed graphs (apg) and states that two hypersets are equal if and only if they can be pictured by the same apg. Within this framework, it can be shown that the equation x = {x} has one and only one solution, the unique Quine atom of the theory.
Each of the axioms given above extends the universe of the previous, so that: V ⊆ A ⊆ S ⊆ F ⊆ B. In the Boffa universe, the distinct Quine atoms form a proper class.[13]
It is worth emphasizing that hyperset theory is an extension of classical set theory rather than a replacement: the well-founded sets within a hyperset domain conform to classical set theory.
Applications
editIn published research, non-well-founded sets are also called hypersets, in parallel to the hyperreal numbers of nonstandard analysis.[14][15]
The hypersets were extensively used by Jon Barwise and John Etchemendy in their 1987 book The Liar, on the liar's paradox. The book's proposals contributed to the theory of truth.[14] The book is also a good introduction to the topic of non-well-founded sets.[14]
See also
editNotes
edit- ^ Pakkan & Akman (1994), section link.
- ^ Rathjen (2004).
- ^ Sangiorgi (2011), pp. 17–19, 26.
- ^ Ballard & Hrbáček (1992).
- ^ Levy (2012), p. 68.
- ^ Hallett (1986), p. 186.
- ^ a b Aczel (1988), p. 105.
- ^ Mirimanoff (1917).
- ^ Aczel (1988), p. 107.
- ^ Aczel (1988), pp. 107–8.
- ^ Aczel (1988), pp. 108–9.
- ^ Aczel (1988), p. 110.
- ^ Nitta, Okada & Tzouvaras (2003).
- ^ a b c Moss, Lawrence S. (2018), "Non-wellfounded Set Theory", in Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2018 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 2024-05-30
- ^ Hypersets (ucsd.edu)
References
edit- Aczel, Peter (1988), Non-Well-Founded Sets, CSLI Lecture Notes, vol. 14, Stanford, CA: Stanford University, Center for the Study of Language and Information, pp. xx+137, ISBN 0-937073-22-9, MR 0940014.
- Ballard, David; Hrbáček, Karel (1992), "Standard foundations for nonstandard analysis", Journal of Symbolic Logic, 57 (2): 741–748, doi:10.2307/2275304, JSTOR 2275304, S2CID 39158351.
- Barwise, Jon; Etchemendy, John (1987), The Liar: An Essay on Truth and Circularity, Oxford University Press, ISBN 9780195059441
- Barwise, Jon; Moss, Lawrence S. (1996), Vicious circles. On the mathematics of non-wellfounded phenomena, CSLI Lecture Notes, vol. 60, CSLI Publications, ISBN 1-57586-009-0
- Boffa., M. (1968), "Les ensembles extraordinaires", Bulletin de la Société Mathématique de Belgique, 20: 3–15, Zbl 0179.01602
- Boffa, M. (1972), "Forcing et négation de l'axiome de Fondement", Acad. Roy. Belgique, Mém. Cl. Sci., Coll. 8∘, Série II, 40 (7), Zbl 0286.02068
- Devlin, Keith (1993), "§7. Non-Well-Founded Set Theory", The Joy of Sets: Fundamentals of Contemporary Set Theory (2nd ed.), Springer, ISBN 978-0-387-94094-6
- Finsler, P. (1926), "Über die Grundlagen der Mengenlehre. I: Die Mengen und ihre Axiome", Math. Z., 25: 683–713, doi:10.1007/BF01283862, JFM 52.0192.01; translation in Finsler, Paul; Booth, David (1996). Finsler Set Theory: Platonism and Circularity : Translation of Paul Finsler's Papers on Set Theory with Introductory Comments. Springer. ISBN 978-3-7643-5400-8.
- Hallett, Michael (1986), Cantorian set theory and limitation of size, Oxford University Press, ISBN 9780198532835.
- Kanovei, Vladimir; Reeken, Michael (2004), Nonstandard Analysis, Axiomatically, Springer, ISBN 978-3-540-22243-9
- Levy, Azriel (2012) [2002], Basic set theory, Dover Publications, ISBN 9780486150734.
- Mirimanoff, D. (1917), "Les antinomies de Russell et de Burali-Forti et le probleme fondamental de la theorie des ensembles", L'Enseignement Mathématique, 19: 37–52, JFM 46.0306.01.
- Nitta, Takashi; Okada, Tomoko; Tzouvaras, Athanassios (2003), "Classification of non-well-founded sets and an application" (PDF), Mathematical Logic Quarterly, 49 (2): 187–200, doi:10.1002/malq.200310018, MR 1961461
- Pakkan, M. J.; Akman, V. (1994), "Issues in commonsense set theory" (PDF), Artificial Intelligence Review, 8 (4): 279–308, doi:10.1007/BF00849061, hdl:11693/25955, S2CID 6323872
- Rathjen, M. (2004), "Predicativity, Circularity, and Anti-Foundation" (PDF), in Link, Godehard (ed.), One Hundred Years of Russell ́s Paradox: Mathematics, Logic, Philosophy, Walter de Gruyter, ISBN 978-3-11-019968-0
- Sangiorgi, Davide (2011), "Origins of bisimulation and coinduction", in Sangiorgi, Davide; Rutten, Jan (eds.), Advanced Topics in Bisimulation and Coinduction, Cambridge University Press, ISBN 978-1-107-00497-9
- Scott, Dana (1960), "A different kind of model for set theory", Unpublished paper, talk given at the 1960 Stanford Congress of Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science
Further reading
edit- Moss, Lawrence S. (2018). "Non-wellfounded Set Theory". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
External links
edit- Metamath page on the axiom of Regularity. Fewer than 1% of that database's theorems are ultimately dependent on this axiom, as can be shown by a command ("show usage") in the Metamath program.