Maximal lotteries

(Redirected from Maximal lottery)

Maximal lotteries refers to a probabilistic voting rule. The method uses preferential ballots and returns a probability distribution (or linear combination) of candidates that a majority of voters would weakly prefer to any other.[1]

Maximal lotteries satisfy a wide range of desirable properties: they elect the Condorcet winner with probability 1 if it exists[1] and never elect candidates outside the Smith set.[1] Moreover, they satisfy reinforcement,[2] participation,[3] and independence of clones.[2] The probabilistic voting rule that returns all maximal lotteries is the only rule satisfying reinforcement, Condorcet-consistency, and independence of clones.[2] The social welfare function that top-ranks maximal lotteries has been uniquely characterized using Arrow's independence of irrelevant alternatives and Pareto efficiency.[4]

Maximal lotteries do not satisfy the standard notion of strategyproofness, as Allan Gibbard has shown that only random dictatorships can satisfy strategyproofness and ex post efficiency.[5] Maximal lotteries are also nonmonotonic in probabilities, i.e. it is possible that the probability of an alternative decreases when a voter ranks this alternative up.[1] However, they satisfy relative monotonicity, i.e., the probability of relative to that of does not decrease when is improved over .[6]

The support of maximal lotteries, which is known as the essential set or the bipartisan set, has been studied in detail.[7][8][9][10]

History

edit

Maximal lotteries were first proposed by the French mathematician and social scientist Germain Kreweras in 1965[11] and popularized by Peter Fishburn.[1] Since then, they have been rediscovered multiple times by economists,[8] mathematicians,[1][12] political scientists, philosophers,[13] and computer scientists.[14]

Several natural dynamics that converge to maximal lotteries have been observed in biology, physics, chemistry, and machine learning.[15][16][17]

Collective preferences over lotteries

edit

The input to this voting system consists of the agents' ordinal preferences over outcomes (not lotteries over alternatives), but a relation on the set of lotteries can be constructed in the following way: if   and   are lotteries over alternatives,   if the expected value of the margin of victory of an outcome selected with distribution   in a head-to-head vote against an outcome selected with distribution   is positive. In other words,   if it is more likely that a randomly selected voter will prefer the alternatives sampled from   to the alternative sampled from   than vice versa.[4] While this relation is not necessarily transitive, it does always admit at least one maximal element.

It is possible that several such maximal lotteries exist, as a result of ties. However, the maximal lottery is unique whenever there the number of voters is odd.[18] By the same argument, the bipartisan set is uniquely-defined by taking the support of the unique maximal lottery that solves a tournament game.[8]

Strategic interpretation

edit

Maximal lotteries are equivalent to mixed maximin strategies (or Nash equilibria) of the symmetric zero-sum game given by the pairwise majority margins. As such, they have a natural interpretation in terms of electoral competition between two political parties[19] and can be computed in polynomial time via linear programming.

Example

edit

Suppose there are five voters who have the following preferences over three alternatives:

  • 2 voters:  
  • 2 voters:  
  • 1 voter:  

The pairwise preferences of the voters can be represented in the following skew-symmetric matrix, where the entry for row   and column   denotes the number of voters who prefer   to   minus the number of voters who prefer   to  .

 

This matrix can be interpreted as a zero-sum game and admits a unique Nash equilibrium (or minimax strategy)   where  ,  ,  . By definition, this is also the unique maximal lottery of the preference profile above. The example was carefully chosen not to have a Condorcet winner. Many preference profiles admit a Condorcet winner, in which case the unique maximal lottery will assign probability 1 to the Condorcet winner. If the last voter in the example above swaps alternatives   and   in his preference relation,   becomes the Condorcet winner and will be selected with probability 1.

References

edit
  1. ^ a b c d e f P. C. Fishburn. Probabilistic social choice based on simple voting comparisons. Review of Economic Studies, 51(4):683–692, 1984.
  2. ^ a b c F. Brandl, F. Brandt, and H. G. Seedig. Consistent probabilistic social choice. Econometrica. 84(5), pages 1839-1880, 2016.
  3. ^ F. Brandl, F. Brandt, and J. Hofbauer. Welfare Maximization Entices Participation. Games and Economic Behavior. 14, pages 308-314, 2019.
  4. ^ a b F. Brandl and F. Brandt. Arrovian Aggregation of Convex Preferences. Econometrica. 88(2), pages 799-844, 2020.
  5. ^ Gibbard, Allan (1977). "Manipulation of Schemes that Mix Voting with Chance". Econometrica. 45 (3): 665–681. doi:10.2307/1911681. hdl:10419/220534. ISSN 0012-9682. JSTOR 1911681.
  6. ^ Brandl, Florian; Brandt, Felix; Stricker, Christian (2022-01-01). "An analytical and experimental comparison of maximal lottery schemes". Social Choice and Welfare. 58 (1): 5–38. doi:10.1007/s00355-021-01326-x. hdl:10419/286729. ISSN 1432-217X.
  7. ^ B. Dutta and J.-F. Laslier. Comparison functions and choice correspondences. Social Choice and Welfare, 16: 513–532, 1999.
  8. ^ a b c G. Laffond, J.-F. Laslier, and M. Le Breton. The bipartisan set of a tournament game. Games and Economic Behavior, 5(1):182–201, 1993.
  9. ^ Laslier, J.-F. Tournament solutions and majority voting Springer-Verlag, 1997.
  10. ^ F. Brandt, M. Brill, H. G. Seedig, and W. Suksompong. On the structure of stable tournament solutions. Economic Theory, 65(2):483–507, 2018.
  11. ^ G. Kreweras. Aggregation of preference orderings. In Mathematics and Social Sciences I: Proceedings of the seminars of Menthon-Saint-Bernard, France (1–27 July 1960) and of Gösing, Austria (3–27 July 1962), pages 73–79, 1965.
  12. ^ D. C. Fisher and J. Ryan. Tournament games and positive tournaments. Journal of Graph Theory, 19(2):217–236, 1995.
  13. ^ D. S. Felsenthal and M. Machover. After two centuries should Condorcet’s voting procedure be implemented? Behavioral Science, 37(4):250–274, 1992.
  14. ^ R. L. Rivest and E. Shen. An optimal single-winner preferential voting system based on game theory. In Proceedings of 3rd International Workshop on Computational Social Choice, pages 399–410, 2010.
  15. ^ B. Laslier and J.-F. Laslier. Reinforcement learning from comparisons: Three alternatives are enough, two are not. Annals of Applied Probability 27(5): 2907–2925, 2017.
  16. ^ Jacopo Grilli, György Barabás, Matthew J. Michalska-Smith and Stefano Allesina. Higher-order interactions stabilize dynamics in competitive network models. Nature 548: 210-214, 2017.
  17. ^ F. Brandl and F. Brandt. A Natural Adaptive Process for Collective Decision-Making. Theoretical Economics 19(2): 667–703, 2024.
  18. ^ Gilbert Laffond, Jean-François Laslier and Michel Le Breton A theorem on two–player symmetric zero–sum games. Journal of Economic Theory 72: 426–431, 1997.
  19. ^ Laslier, J.-F. Interpretation of electoral mixed strategies. Social Choice and Welfare 17: pages 283–292, 2000.
edit
  • voting.ml (website for computing maximal lotteries)